![]() |
Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
Indigenous Law Bulletin |
![]() |
The further use of military force to combat child abuse, and a
return to the paternalistic policies of the past, indicates that the
policies of
forced assimilation, dispossession and racial discrimination have returned to
Australia. So concerned was the previous
Government that the Intervention may be
found to be racially discriminatory that it was exempted from the provisions of
the Racial Discrimination Act 1975 (Cth) (‘RDA’). It is
likely that collective punishment of people of a particular race would be found
to be discriminatory
under that
Act.[5] Military and para-military
responses to allegations of child abuse run dangerously close to reviving
previous policies of forcible
removal.
What is remarkable is that the
Labor Party, initially critical of the Intervention, ultimately supported it in
all legislative points.
More than a year into the new Government’s
parliamentary term, it is notable that it has not modified that policy or
amended
the legislation, despite an earlier commitment to bring it within the
purview of the RDA. Critical of the Intervention, Larissa Behrendt
asked one
year ago what the Government was going to do after the
Apology.[6] I consider that offering
an apology, without addressing any of the concerns over the Intervention, shows
not only a lack of commitment
or follow through, but also betrays a dangerous
lack of attention to the very concerns that led to the Apology in the first
place.
Before considering the way in which Mr Rudd dealt with issues of
responsibility, I will briefly consider some theoretical issues surrounding
law
and responsibility. A traditional view sees law as a technique for attaching
responsibility. Scott Veitch follows Nicola Lacey
in proposing an alternative
view of law as a technology of social organisation. That is, Veitch considers
that law disperses responsibilities to such an extent that it becomes a
technology for ‘the legitimation of human suffering’. Law’s
‘technologies of responsibility’, working within the ‘broader
social forms of power, also provide some of the major
resources through which
dispersals and disavowals of responsibility in society can occur’. The
contrast between the isolated
post-Enlightenment individual and the dominance of
social institutions produces a ‘proliferation of
irresponsibilities’.[7] The
result is ‘the irresponsible mentality’, fostered in the individual
who is buffetted by illusions of choice and autonomy
but is, in reality,
powerless.[8]
The historical
dimension to this bleak critique traces changes from ancient Greek conceptions
of responsibility, through to the individualisation
of the self-conscious
‘moral agent’ of the Enlightenment. Veitch transposes these into a
post-modern world marked by
‘a plurality of social systems, and their
offerings and solutions’. So, if the ancient heroes did not know
responsibility
because they were playthings of fate and the gods, we moderns
fail to respond to those now well-known responsibilities by being tossed
about
by social systems. But despite the interference of fate and the gods in ancient
Greek epics, their notion of responsibility
was a ‘thick’ one,
imputing to the actor the consequences of those actions, and bringing
with it ‘the obligation to compensate or submit to
punishment’.[9] This is in
contrast to the ‘thin’, modern idea of responsibility which, Ricoeur
proposes, takes no account of the broad
issues of moral responsibility, relying
instead on a narrow conception of legal responsibility. Being responsible in a
purely legal
sense allows us to mitigate our culpability and offset our
liability through ‘technologies of responsibility’, among
which
Veitch includes consumer economy, administrative decision making, accounting and
auditing[10] that have replaced the
ancient gods. This state of dispersed responsibility calls for a reassessment of
law and ethics. Can we imagine
a moral actor who is self-conscious but not
isolated from others?
Desmond Manderson has drawn the distinction
between this thin responsibility to a generalised other, and the relationship of
proximity.
He insists that law is based in the ethical relationship, the duty of
care one owes to a specific other. The arrangements of reciprocity define
the boundaries of the self and the other, so that the individual is recognised
through
his or her reciprocal relations, of gift or contract. Veitch’s
critique of law’s role in the allocation of responsibility
finds it
fundamentally compromised by a society of nominally free individuals who are
disempowered by technologies that disperse
responsibilities.
Our
responsibilities to others have been mediated by social relations and
collectivities. We have many of the characteristics of the
Enlightenment
individual: we are self-conscious and we recognise our specificity as persons
and as legal subjects. Yet, as members
of collectivities, we recognise the
constraints on our actions, that our free will is not absolute. Let us see how
this interplay
of responsibility, moral consciousness and legal technologies
plays out in the Rudd Government’s apology and subsequent
responses.
The Apology expressly invokes the responsibility of parliaments to absolve
any individual of responsibility. As the Prime Minister
said:
We, the
parliaments of the nation, are ultimately responsible, not those who gave effect
to our laws. The problem lay with the laws
themselves.
There can be
no question of agency in this account: people who implemented policies of child
removal, even those ‘protectors
of natives’ who stand condemned by
their genocidal statements quoted by Mr
Rudd,[11] were merely ‘giving
effect’ to laws. There is no opening here for inquiries into individual
responsibility or culpability,
of the sort that motivated South Africa’s
or Canada’s Truth and Reconciliation Commissions.
Mr Rudd did,
however, concede that there were certain relevant ‘intergenerational
responsibilities’. He went on from laying
the blame on the laws to refer
to the ‘many blessings [we like other settler societies have received]
from our ancestors, and
therefore we must also be the bearer of their burdens as
well.' These ancestors and their euphemistically named ‘blessings’
were not so remote. Mr Rudd pointed out that the policies of child removal
continued into the 1970s, when some current members of
Parliament were first
elected, a period ‘well within the adult memory span of many of us’.
Yet the language of ‘ancestors’
and ‘memory spans’ still
manages to deflect responsibility. An ‘adult memory span’ presumably
refers to events
in our adult lives, to a period in which we were
‘responsible’ in a legal sense, in which we were electing
responsible
parliamentary representatives, some of whom, as Mr Rudd points out,
are still sitting in the Parliament.
The PM referred to another sort of
responsibility, that of ‘national responsibility’, in support of his
proposal to develop
bi-partisan policies agreed with the opposition. Apart from
the fact that this approach was quickly rejected by the opposition, it
was
hardly one likely to inspire confidence among Indigenous communities and others
concerned to pursue respectful, egalitarian policies,
given the
coalition’s record on Indigenous affairs over its eleven year rule.
Particularly troubling was the PM’s choice
of words for forming a
bi-partisan approach. We need, he said ‘a kind of war cabinet on
parts of Indigenous
policy’.[12] The last time the
Labor Party and Coalition joined forces to declare war on Indigenous communities
was when they sent the troops
into the Northern Territory in 2007.
In all
the rhetoric about the responsibilities of parliaments, the agency of laws
(‘and not of men’, to paraphrase the
rule of law
doctrine[13]) and the workings of
time to allocate to ‘ancestors’ the ‘blessings’ we
settlers have received from dispossession
of others’ land, one anecdote
stands out. It is the only point at which Mr Rudd personalised the question of
responsibility,
apology and retribution. In response to his own rhetorical
question, ‘Why apologise?’, Mr Rudd took six of the total
24
paragraphs of his speech to tell the story of Nanna Nungala Fejo, stolen from
her family in about 1932.[14] It is
a characteristically appalling story of broken families and inhumanity, in which
the agency for ‘giving effect to those
laws’ is specifically
allocated to ‘a truck, two white men and an Aboriginal stockman on
horseback cracking his stockwhip’.
The punch line should be quoted in
detail:
Nanna Fejo took one of my staff aside, wanting to make sure
that I was not too hard on the Aboriginal stockman who had hunted those
kids
down all those years ago. The stockman had found her again decades later, this
time himself to say, ‘Sorry.’ And
remarkably, extraordinarily, she
had forgiven him.
We know nothing of what the white men were doing,
though the truck presumably did not drive itself; certainly, it is unlikely that
the stockman, whip or no whip, ‘hunted those kids down’ and put them
on the truck all by himself. Mr Rudd’s point,
of course, is that, even
were we to find an agent (and how convenient that this one is Aboriginal), he
can now be forgiven. Indeed,
he should be forgiven because Nanna Fejo
forgave him and wanted to make sure the PM was ‘not too hard on
him’. This is a parable
of biblical credentials: sins and sinners, guilt
and forgiveness, a scapegoat chosen to bear the guilt of a whole community. With
this device, the whole question of agency is dispatched, leaving the field open
to parliaments, laws and other nameless institutions
to act as technologies to
disperse responsibility.
What, then, are we to make of an apology that pledges never to repeat past
injustices while failing to respond, to allocate responsibility,
or to accept
responsibility for repetition of such a policy? What are we to make of the pride
that so many Australians felt in celebrating
that apology? The distress and
outrage felt by many Australians over the previous Government’s failure to
apologise to the
Stolen Generations, and the many spontaneous expressions of
apology, indicate a widespread sense of collective responsibility. We
respond
when faced with the evidence of the unspeakable suffering of Indigenous people,
many of them of our own generation. We must
assess the adequacy of the
response.
The impersonality of law and the overarching power of the
Parliament can be seen, as they are by Veitch, to deprive us of personal
responsibility. Yet if ethical life is to continue, we must also see ourselves
as persons with responsibilities to others. Whether
we were duped by the law,
the parliament, or, like the ancient Greeks by the gods, we must still see the
consequences of our actions;
‘good intentions’ or institutional
imperatives cannot completely absolve us.
Reciprocity, as Ricoeur and
Manderson point out, involves recognition of the between: this includes
the relations between connected persons, persons with a continuity of life
experience, be that of suffering and loss
of family or of active participation
in removing children. Yet whether or not we individually participated in the
removal of children,
or any of the earlier crimes, we are also connected as
inhabitants of the same social and physical space. To recognise that one is
the
beneficiary of the alienation of another’s land, which entailed the
destruction of many cultures and the denial of their
law, is to be disturbed by
profound doubts about the moral foundation of one’s own culture, law and
well-being.
The Apology addressed only the first of the actions proposed
by the Bringing Them Home report. Beyond acknowledgment and apology, the
report also recommended ‘guarantees against repetition, measures of
restitution,
measures of rehabilitation, and monetary
compensation.’[15] A tort
which, as Manderson notes, is at the heart of our relationship to the other,
cannot simply be swept away by the acceptance
of a generalised responsibility.
That responsibility has consequences for the other, which must include redress,
allocation of responsibility,
and reparations. Not only did the Apology fail to
address the question of reparations, but the Government’s subsequent
actions
give no confidence that it can – or will – guarantee against
repetition of genocidal practices.
The Intervention into Aboriginal
communities continues to run that risk of repetition. It does this by
overturning land rights, by
collective punishment of whole communities
(exclusively Aboriginal) by quarantining of income, by sending in contingents of
police
and soldiers to ‘combat’ child abuse. If these actions were,
indeed, well intended, and were not racially discriminatory,
then at least they
would have to be exposed to the test of the RDA. That they are still screened
from its operation indicates a complete
lack of responsibility taken for their
impact on a race of people. On 13 October 2008, the Minister released the report
of the Northern
Territory Emergency Response Review Board. While generally
supporting the Intervention as a response to a genuine ‘national
emergency’, the Review recommended improved cooperation with Indigenous
communities, making the income management scheme voluntary
and that all
Government actions should ‘respect Australia’s human rights
obligations and conform with the Racial Discrimination Act
1975’.[16]
While
apologising for, and making good on, our responsibilities for past wrongs, we
must also look forward; we must properly comprehend
the risk of repeating our
genocidal past. To continue racist and potentially genocidal policies
constitutes an ethical betrayal and
a refusal of responsibility. We still
possess a language of responsibility; we must use it to try to recognise how we
should respond
to past injustices and respond ethically and intelligently,
rather than with blind belligerence to current and future challenges.
Richard Mohr is Senior Lecturer and Director of the Legal Intersections Research Centre, University of Wollongong. The final version of this article was completed as a visiting researcher at the Judicial Systems Research Institute (IRSIG-CNR), Bologna with the support of the Short Term Mobility program of the Consiglio Nazionale delle Ricerche (Italy).
[1] Human Rights and Equal
Opportunities Commission, Bringing Them Home (1997) available at
<http://www.hreoc.gov.au/education/bth/community_guide/index.html at 22 April 2008>
.
[2] Commonwealth of
Australia, Parliamentary Debates, House of Representatives, Wednesday
13 February 2008, 170 (Kevin Rudd, Prime Minister) henceforth
‘Hansard’.
[3]
Sen. Concetta Fieravanti-Wells, quoted Michelle Hoctor, ‘Walkout
Explained’, Illawarra Mercury (Wollongong), 15 February
2008.
[4] Lindsay Murdoch and
Katharine Murphy, ‘Canberra's NT Troop Move
“Devastating”’, The Age (Melbourne) 6 August 2007,
available at
<http://www.theage.com.au/news/national/canberras-nt-troop-move-devastating/2007/08/05/1186252546287.html>
.
[5]
Desmond Manderson, ‘Not Yet: Aboriginal People and the Deferral of the
Rule of Law’ (2008) 29/30 Arena 219,
243-245.
[6] Larissa Behrendt, UTS
Speaks, 19 March 2008, available at
<http://www.jumbunna.uts.edu.au/research/pdf/UTSSpeaksLarissa.pdf>
.
[7]
Scott Veitch Law and Irresponsibility: On the Legitimation of Human
Suffering (2007), 41.
[8] Ibid
55-6.
[9] Paul Ricoeur Parcours
de la Reconnaissance: Trois Études (2004)
177.
[10] Veitch, above n 7,
58.
[11] ’The problem of
our half-castes … will quickly be eliminated by the complete disappearance
of the black race, and the
swift submergence of their progeny in the white
...’ (Northern Territory Protector of Natives, similar to views of the
Western
Australian Protector of Natives) quoted Hansard above n 2,
169.
[12] Hansard, above n
2, 172.
[13] Restated by
Blackburn J. in Milirrpum v. Nabalco (1971) 17 FLR 141,
267.
[14] Hansard above n
2, 169.
[15] HREOC, above n 1,
Appendices 9.
[16] Northern
Territory Emergency Response Review Board, Report of the NTER Review
Board, 30 September 2008, Australian Government, Canberra, 12.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/IndigLawB/2009/13.html