Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
University of Melbourne Law School Research Series |
Last Updated: 15 July 2010
FREEDOM OF POLITICAL COMMUNICATION, THE CONSTITUTION AND THE COMMON LAW
Adrienne Stone[*]
INTRODUCTION
Perhaps the most remarkable feature of Australian constitutional development
in the past decade has been the advent of the constitutional
protection of
political
communication.[1] One
important effect of this development has been to focus Australian constitutional
debate on the long standing and rich tradition
of constitutional protection of
speech in the United States. Reference to American constitutional law is not
unprecedented. The
United States Constitution has long been a source for
Australian constitutional lawyers. It was extensively referred to by the
framers of the Australian
Constitution[2] and over
the century since the framing, it has been a constant point of reference for the
High Court of
Australia.[3] However,
the influence of the First Amendment is particularly significant since the Bill
of Rights and the other rights provisions
of the United States Constitution have
traditionally been thought of as a part of the American constitutional tradition
which Australia does not
share.[4]
The
influence of American constitutional jurisprudence, and specifically First
Amendment law, in the High Court of Australia has
never been more significant
than in the most adventurous of its decisions on the freedom of political
communication: Theophanous v Herald and Weekly Times
[5] and Stephens
v West Australian
Newspapers.[6] Here,
the High Court significantly expanded the protection of political communication
by adopting a rule similar to the New York Times v Sullivan
doctrine.[7] That is,
the Court limited the capacity of political figures to bring actions for
defamation. However, most unusually for recent
decisions of the High Court,
these cases were reconsidered and considerably reformulated by the Court only
three years after they
were first announced, in Lange v Australian
Broadcasting
Commission.[8]
The
short life of these cases appears to lend fuel to those who argue against the
use of the American precedent, and specifically
First Amendment jurisprudence,
in interpreting the Australian
Constitution.[9] In
this article, I will join those who have expressed such concerns. My focus,
however, is somewhat different from previous analyses.
I will consider a
difference between the two systems that has been overlooked: the different
jurisdictions of the highest appellate
courts. The High Court, unlike the
Supreme Court of the United States, has jurisdiction to hear appeals from all
courts, state and
federal. In hearing these appeals, it has jurisdiction over
matters of common law as well as federal law and the Constitution. The
significance of the High Court's role as the interpreter of the common law was
highlighted by Theophanous and Stephens. In those cases, argument
was addressed to the High Court on both the protection of freedom of speech by
the Constitution and by the common law of defamation. Had it been so inclined,
the Court could have avoided the constitutional issue entirely through
a
decision on the common law. However, the principal basis of the decision of the
majority was the
Constitution.[10] In
my view, the Court’s failure to appreciate the significance of its common
law jurisdiction helps explain where the High
Court went wrong in Theophanous
and Stephens, and how it might have avoided facing so serious a
challenge to recent cases as it did in Lange.
Before proceeding to
make this point, however, I devote Part I of this article to explaining the
nature and origins of the High Court’s jurisdiction on matters of common
law and compare
it to the jurisdiction of the United States Supreme Court. In
Part II, I outline Theophanous and Stephens and compare the
constitutional approach of the majority to the common law approach of two of the
dissenting Justices. Part III contains the heart of my argument. I consider
how the High Court ought to proceed when a case before it can be decided either
by
the common law or by interpretation of the Constitution. I argue that the
common law brings with it significant advantages so that in many cases where the
two overlap, the High Court ought
to prefer the common law and I use
Theophanous and Stephens to illustrate my point. In Part IV, I
identify more precisely the kinds of cases in which the benefits of a common law
solution should lead the High Court to prefer
it and defend my argument against
some of the most obvious objections to it. Finally, in Part V, I consider the
reformulation of the Theophanous doctrine in Lange and the extent
to which that decision is responsive to the critique I have
launched.
I. THE POWER TO DECIDE THE COMMON LAW - THE HIGH COURT OF
AUSTRALIA AND THE SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
The High Court has a general power to decide matters of common law as a
result of s 73 of the Australian Constitution, which provides that the High
Court shall have jurisdiction to hear appeals from “all judgments,
decrees, orders and sentences
of any . . . federal court, or court exercising
federal jurisdiction, or of the Supreme Court of any
State”.[11] This
provision gives the High Court control over all of the law of Australia,
including the common law as developed by state courts.
By contrast, federal
courts in the United States principally exercise power over federal law, relying
on a grant in Article III of
power over “All Cases, in Law and Equity,
arising under this Constitution, the Laws of the United States and Treaties made
. . . under their Authority”. Under other clauses, such as the grant of
jurisdiction
over cases “between Citizens of different States”,
federal courts have jurisdiction over cases in which state law provides
the rule
of decision. This may require federal courts to decide matters of common law,
but in these cases federal power over state
law is limited. The well known
case Erie RR v Tompkins ensured this by limiting the power of federal
courts in relation to matters of state
law.[12] The Supreme
Court held that because there is no constitutional authority for Congress to act
in some areas in which the federal courts
had been deciding common law cases,
and because the Constitution did not itself bestow such a power on the federal
courts, the assumption by the federal courts of power to decide the common law
was
unconstitutional.[13]
Since Erie, the federal courts have had no general power to develop the
common law. Where state law governs the case, they must follow or
predict[14] the common
law of the relevant
state.[15] The High
Court’s power to exercise its own judgment as to the nature of the common
law and overrule the decisions of the highest
state courts, thus sets it apart
from its United States counterpart.
The consequence is that the Australian
High Court’s jurisdiction does not reflect the federal division of powers
which governs
other constitutional arrangements. As Sir Kenneth Wheare
explained:
If the federal principle were to be strictly applied one would expect a dual system to be established in a federation, one set of courts to apply and interpret the law of the general government, and another to apply and interpret the law of each state.[16]
The historical record reveals two explanations for the less distinctively
federal structure of the Australian federal courts. Perhaps
the dominant
influence on the framers in this regard was the model of the Privy Council
which, prior to the federation of the Australian
colonies, supervised the
development of the common law by colonial courts. Under the Australian
Constitution, it was proposed from the start that the High Court would hear
appeals from all decisions of state
courts.[17]
Consequently the High Court would sit at the apex of the court system as the
Privy Council had over colonial
courts.[18] Although
it was initially proposed that the High Court would replace the Privy
Council,[19] a role
for it was ultimately
preserved.[20] The
result was that the common law remained a unitary system synthesised in
Australia by the High Court and throughout the British
Commonwealth by the Privy
Council.
In addition to consistency with the model of the Privy Council, the
conferral of general appellate jurisdiction on the High Court
made uniformity of
the common law, which had eluded the American federal courts, possible in the
Australian system.[21]
Further, any misgivings about the effect of this arrangement on the federal
balance were apparently allayed by confidence in the
judiciary.[22] Quick
and Garran, in their influential commentary, summarised the basis of s 73:
[I]n Australia, as in Canada, the appellate jurisdiction is not one of those jealously guarded State rights which make anything more intimate than a federal union impossible. We are accustomed to a common court of appeal in the shape of the Privy Council: we are so assured of the independence and integrity of the Bench that the advantages of having one uniform Australian tribunal of final resort outweigh all feelings of localism [.][23]
The jurisdiction of the High Court can therefore be explained by the
framers’ desire to achieve uniformity of the laws, consistency
with the
model of the Privy Council and their confidence that the federal judiciary would
use its power responsibly. What has been
less explored, is how the High Court
ought to proceed in cases in which these bodies of law overlap. To this I
direct the remainder
of this article.
II. DECISION MAKING IN THE HIGH
COURT
Theophanous and Stephens
The Decision
of the Majority in Theophanous and Stephens
Theophanous v Herald
and Weekly
Times[24]
and its companion case Stephens v West Australian
Newspapers[25]
marked a dramatic turn in Australian constitutional law. In these cases the
High Court addressed a question similar to that which
faced the United States
Supreme Court in New York Times v
Sullivan.[26] In
Australian terms the issue was whether the constitutional freedom of political
communication allowed political figures to maintain
an action for defamation.
In Theophanous, which contains most of the reasoning concerning the
freedom of political
communication,[27] the
High Court held that the implied freedom of political communication had a
similar effect to the New York Times v Sullivan rule. That is, it held
that the constitutional implication protecting freedom of political
communication placed limits on the capacity
for political figures to bring
actions for
defamation.[28]
The
Overlap of the Common Law and the Constitution
One of the most
significant features of these decisions was the High Court’s attention to
the relationship between the common
law and Australian constitutional law.
Because of the nature of the Australian Constitution, these bodies of doctrine
had previously operated within largely different realms. The Australian
Constitution is primarily devoted to delineating the extent of federal power,
providing the basic structure of the federal government, the relationship
between the federal government and the states, and the relationship between the
states. The few provisions which protect individual
rights[29] have, at
least until very recently, been narrowly
construed.[30]
Consequently constitutional law has not often dealt with the regulation of
relationships between the individual and the state or
between individuals which
has generally remained the province of the common law. But, once the High Court
ventured into the protection
of communication on political matters, the
possibility of overlap arose, notably with the common law of defamation.
In
Theophanous and Stephens each of the majority justices held that
the Constitution affected the common law, finding that the common law of
defamation was affected by the constitutional requirement of freedom of
political
communication.[31]
This decision aligned the High Court, at least
temporarily,[32] with
the United States Supreme Court rather than its Canadian counter-part. The
Canadian Supreme Court has held that the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms
applies only to legislative, executive and administrative branches of government
and not the common
law.
[33] By contrast, in
the United States, the common law is subject to the First Amendment and most
other guarantees of the Bill of
Rights.[34]
The
Common Law Alternative
Following the decisions in Theophanous
and Stephens then, the reach of the freedom of political
communication under the Australian Constitution appeared to be closer to that of
rights guarantees in the United States Constitution than to the Canadian Charter
of Rights and Freedoms. However, Theophanous and
Stephens demonstrated an important remaining difference between the
United States and Australian positions. Because of the High Court’s
common
law jurisdiction, argument was also addressed to the Court on the operation of
the common law defence of qualified
privilege,[35] and the
High Court had a choice as to how to proceed.
For the majority, the answer to
the constitutional question dictated their approach to the common law: it
followed from their opinion
that the Constitution limited actions for defamation
by political figures, that the common law must give way to the constitutional
requirement of freedom
of political
communication.[36] For
the dissentients,[37]
however, the common law question survived. Having declined to extend the
constitutional protection of communication, the question
remained: did the
common law defence of qualified privilege protect speech relating to public or
political matters? In Theophanous, the dissentients found the question
strictly unnecessary to
decide.[38] In
Stephens, however, two of the Justices dealt with the matter in some
detail. In its traditional form, the defence of qualified privilege
had
excluded publications, such as those in newspapers or broadcasts, which are to
the world at
large.[39] It was
considered that the interest of the general public in information was not
established merely by the fact that it concerned
a matter in which the public
was interested.[40] A
newspaper publication was therefore generally not privileged, because it would
usually carry a communication beyond those who have
a legitimate interest in
it.[41] Of the
dissentients, Justice Brennan and Justice McHugh proposed extensions of the
traditional rule of qualified privilege to cover
some publications to the world
at large. Though they differ in
detail,[42] as I will
later show, each Justice’s response allowed greater protection of
political
communication.[43]
III. THE
COMMON LAW AS AN ALTERNATIVE TO CONSTITUTIONAL CHANGE
My central point is that the common law analysis advanced by Justices Brennan
and McHugh is preferable to the majority’s constitutional
analysis.
However, I make the argument for different reasons than those advanced by their
Honours. Unlike Justices Brennan and
McHugh, I do not argue that the
majority’s constitutional analysis was flawed. Rather, my point is that
regardless of the
correct constitutional analysis, the common law is a
preferable basis for decision because it reduces the risk involved in decision
making. Before I make this argument however, I will make three preliminary
points.
Preliminary Matters
First, it should be stressed that my
criticism is addressed to the High Court’s decisions in Theophanous
and Stephens rather than the United States Supreme Court’s decision
in New York Times. I stress this because, particularly in the light of
its history, it is easy to have sympathy with New York Times. In that
case, the New York Times was sued by an Alabama
official for carrying an advertisement critical of the actions of Alabama
authorities during the American civil
rights movement. As Anthony Lewis
relates, the trial occurred amidst enormous hostility to the New York Times,
which stemmed from
Southern determination to resist the civil rights
movement.[44] The
hostility was such that the New York Times had difficulty finding an Alabama
lawyer to represent it; the jury was made subject
to this hostile feeling by the
publication of their names and faces on the front page of the Alabama
Journal and there is even a suggestion that the trial judge helped plan the
plaintiff’s
action.[45] Finally,
despite the weakness of the plaintiff's
case,[46] the jury
awarded, and the Supreme Court of Alabama upheld, a judgment of $500,000 against
the New York Times. This was the largest
libel judgment in Alabama history and
extraordinary by national
standards.[47]
The
impropriety of the proceedings in Alabama and the racist motivations of many of
those involved seem clear. The case for Supreme
Court intervention was,
therefore, particularly compelling and, moreover, because of its jurisdictional
limitations, the United States
Supreme Court did not have the common law
available to it. My criticism then, is less of the use of constitutional means
to protect
speech in this judgment, than its adoption by the High Court of
Australia where a common law alternative was available.
Secondly, I should
acknowledge at the outset that the High Court’s failure to consider the
common law as an alternative to constitutional
law in Theophanous and
Stephens may result simply from the nature of Australian constitutional
law and from the procedural context of these cases. For the reasons
I have
explained, the common law and Australian constitutional law have not often
overlapped, if at all. Consequently, the idea
of such a choice was quite new
and the High Court’s failure to consider it quite understandable.
Further, these cases came
before the High Court as cases
stated,[48] according
to which the issue of common law qualified privilege only arose if the Court
found that the Constitution protected discussion of government or political
matters from defamation
action.[49]
Consequently, the consideration of the constitutional issue naturally came
before the consideration of the common law issue.
However, this point has
little significance for my argument. Although it explains why the High Court
failed to consider the common
law as an alternative to constitutional decision
making, it does not undermine the point that the common law was a more
appropriate
basis for decision. My concern is not to prove the High
Court’s lack of foresight but to show how use of the common law would
have
improved its decision making.
Finally, I should acknowledge that the idea
that constitutional decision making should be avoided, where another ground of
decision
is available, is familiar. In the United States and Australia there
have long been rules that counsel avoidance of constitutional
decision making
through the preference of a non-constitutional ground of
decision.[50] An
example is the rule that a court should, where fairly possible, prefer a
construction of a statute that is consistent with the
Constitution, rather than
the review of the statute against the
Constitution.[51]
The
approach I am proposing could be seen as a common law version of this statutory
rule. Perhaps it could roughly be expressed as
follows: a court should, where
fairly possible, prefer a construction of the common law that is consistent with
the Constitution, rather than the enunciation of a constitutional standard to
replace an unconstitutional common law standard.
Given its relationship to
arguments for constitutional avoidance in other contexts, the rule of common law
preference may find justification
in some arguments traditionally made in favour
of constitutional avoidance. The most prominent of these relies on the
“counter-majoritarian”
nature of judicial
review.[52] The
argument is that, because judicial review thwarts the power of elected branches
and is not easily reviewable by democratic
means,[53] it should
be used sparingly. In addition, concerns over the political vulnerability of
courts,[54] their
limited capacity to fashion and enforce
solutions,[55] and the
desire to show proper respect to other branches of the federal
government[56] and to
the states,[57] have
inspired further arguments for judicial restraint in respect of constitutional
decision making.
Although these arguments might seem to support my thesis,
I do not seek to rely them here. First, there is a question as to the extent
that these concerns are relevant when the High Court is considering the
constitutionality of the common law. After all, the common
law is not so
obviously the result of a majoritarian process. Moreover, if the High Court
decides upon the constitutionality of
some common law doctrine, it is not
interfering with the decisions of other branches of the state or federal
governments but with
judge made doctrine. At most, a decision on the
constitutional issue has counter-majoritarian implications through its power to
restrain the future legislative and executive
action.[58] More
fundamentally, however, I do not rely on such arguments because I am interested
in another reason for constitutional avoidance
that applies particularly when
the alternative basis of the decision making is the common law. As I have
stated, my argument is that
the common law reduces the risks of decision making
and is more likely, therefore, to produce a good substantive result.
The Risk Posed by Theophanous and
Stephens
Theophanous and Stephens are
important decisions on matters of high public importance. In advancing a
vision of constitutionally protected communication and a
rule according to which
such communication is protected from defamation, the High Court has made some
important commitments. As
I will now show, in taking such an important stand,
the High Court has made commitments that may later be
regretted.[59]
The
Philosophical Basis of the Freedom of Political Communication
One of
the most important aspects of these decisions is the development of a
philosophy to explain the freedom of political communication. One important
influence on
the High Court is the United States Supreme Court’s
interpretation of the First Amendment. This entailed a high degree of
protection for speech because, as is well known, First Amendment jurisprudence
is characterised by scepticism of government regulation
of speech. Among the
strongest manifestations of this scepticism are the subjection of much
regulation of speech to an exacting
standard of review known as “strict
scrutiny”[60]
and a distrust of any role government might have in improving the quality of
public
discourse.[61]
This
hostility to government intervention is evident in the early High Court cases on
the freedom of political communication. On
the issue of the standard of review,
a majority of the High Court initially adopted an approach that closely
resembled American free
speech law. In Australian Capital Television,
Chief Justice Mason and Justice McHugh drew a distinction between
“restrictions on communication which target ideas or information
and those
which restrict an activity or mode of communication by which ideas or
information are
transmitted.”[62]
In the first category, content based regulation, both Justices used language
reminiscent of the “compelling interest”
requirement of the American
strict scrutiny
standard.[63] A
similar standard was articulated by Justices Deane and
Toohey.[64]
The
protectiveness of this approach can be contrasted with that of Justice Brennan,
who was far more sympathetic to regulation.
He articulated a single
proportionality requirement which is applicable to all regulation of speech.
The validity of legislation
is determined by the “proportionality between
the restriction which a law imposes on the freedom of communication and the
legitimate
interest which the law is intended to
serve.”[65]
Moreover, he stressed the “supervisory” role of the
Court[66] and
concluded that it should allow the Parliament a “margin of
appreciation”[67]
in assessing the need for regulation.
Further influence of the American
model of free speech can be seen in the High Court’s position on
regulation designed to improve
the quality of political discourse. In contrast
to the United States Supreme
Court,[68] in
Australian Capital
Television,[69]
Chief Justice Mason and Justices Deane and Toohey indicated that the High Court
may entertain the argument that such regulation of
communication is
justified.[70]
However, the Chief Justice expressed a level of scepticism which might be
familiar to a student of the First Amendment:
[T]he Court should scrutinize very carefully any claim that the freedom of communication must be restricted in order to protect the integrity of the political process . . . All too often attempts to restrict the freedom in the name of some imagined necessity have tended to stifle public discussion and criticism of government. The Court should be astute not to accept at face value claims . . . that freedom of communication will, unless curtailed, bring about corruption and distortion of the political process.[71]
In the end, moreover, each of these Justices found the legislation in
Australian Capital Television
wanting.[72] Only
Justice Brennan, whose approach was particularly deferential to the legislature,
upheld the legislation on that
basis.[73]
Theophanous and Stephens, then, represent an extension of
this influence of the First Amendment in Australia. The High Court was
explicitly influenced by
New York Times v Sullivan, adopting its analysis
of the chilling effect of libel action on
speech.[74]
This
attention to First Amendment jurisprudence is perhaps explained by an underlying
philosophical affinity. One of the most influential
ideas underlying the First
Amendment is a belief that free speech supports
democracy.[75] Free
speech is valued because it allows citizens to get information about their
government; to hold their governments accountable
to them and exercise choice as
to who governs them. Moreover, it assists citizens in communicating their
wishes to their government,
enabling governments to be more
responsive.[76] New
York Times v Sullivan clearly reflects the link between freedom of speech
and democratic values. Freedom of expression on public issues is secured
because
“the First Amendment ‘was fashioned to assure unfettered
interchange of ideas for the bringing about of political and
social changes
desired by the
people.’”[77]
As the Australian freedom of political communication is derived from the notion
of representative
democracy,[78] it
appears to have a similar philosophical foundation and the adoption of New
York Times, or rather a form of that rule, may be explained on that
basis.
However, a commitment to the protection of democracy need not
have led the High Court to adopt New York Times and the strong stand
against regulation embodied in that case. That attitude to regulation of speech
is attributable to other aspects
of First Amendment theory which the freedom of
political communication may not share. A central feature of New York
Times is the Supreme Court’s decision to protect false
defamatory information. The Court held that a defence where truth is proved
does not satisfy the First
Amendment.[79] The
Court acknowledged that false statements will be
made[80] and
reputations will be damaged by
them.[81] However, it
held that the injury to reputation does not justify regulation of speech by the
law of libel. The Court quoted the Supreme
Court of
Kansas:[82]
It is of the utmost consequence that the people should discuss the character and qualifications of candidates for their suffrages. The importance to the state and to society of such discussions is so vast and the advantages derived are so great, that they more than counterbalance the inconvenience of private persons whose conduct may be involved, and occasional injury to the reputations of individuals must yield to the public welfare, although at times such injury may be great.
It may be that freedom of political communication must protect communication
in the face of some harms which, in other circumstances,
would justify
regulation. Professor Blasi has argued that the protection of speech, even
though it causes harm, is an essential
part of the notion that freedom of speech
serves democracy.[83]
However, the particular decision made by the Supreme Court in New York
Times, that the harm caused by false speech does not outweigh the interest
in free speech need not be accepted by the High Court. As Professor
Blasi
explains, “exponents of the self-government theory [of the First
Amendment] may reach rather different conclusions regarding
what harms can serve
as a justification for limiting freedom of
speech.”[84]
The
Supreme Court’s conclusion in New York Times is strongly influenced
by the notion of “the market place of ideas” which draws on Justice
Holmes’ famous argument
that “the best test of truth is the power of
the thought to get itself accepted in the competition of the
market”.[85] In
its strongest form, the belief is that only the truth will survive competition
between ideas.[86]
Another version, most famously articulated by John Stuart Mill, points to the
fallibility of human knowledge and the consequent value
in subjecting our
beliefs to
contradiction.[87]
Professor Schauer has suggested a third and more limited version of the
argument. He argues that speech should be unregulated because
there is reason
to be especially sceptical about the motives and abilities of government in
determining which information should
circulate and which should be
suppressed.[88]
According to this analysis, the case for free speech reflects, not a faith that
the market place of ideas will produce the truth,
but a belief that it is
“the most viable alternative to authoritative
decree.”[89]
This argument suggests that the importance of free speech lies in its power to
prevent authoritarianism.
The high value the Supreme Court places on freedom
of speech in New York Times reflects the influence of these various
arguments for a free market place of ideas. The belief that debate must
be “uninhibited, robust and wide-open”, that it requires
“vigor” and
“variety”[90]
appears to value the competition and contradiction of the “market place of
ideas”. Indeed, Schauer’s form of the
argument, the notion that a
“free market” in ideas is the only reliable alternative to
authoritarian control of speech
is evident in the Supreme Court’s citation
of Learned Hand’s statement, that the First Amendment “presupposes
that
right conclusions are more likely to be gathered out of a multitude of
tongues, than through any kind of authoritative
selection.”[91]
It
is this part of the American free speech tradition that the High Court could
have rejected consistently with its commitment to
representative democracy.
American scholars have shown that the relationship between democracy and freedom
of speech can be seen
differently. Some American commentators, who value
freedom of speech for its capacity to promote public deliberation, have argued
that the current American approach is not consistent with that ideal. In
particular, it neglects the distorting effect of existing
inequalities in access
to information and the capacity to
communicate.[92]
Consequently, protecting speech from regulation may hinder rather than advance
public debate by excluding the voices of some and
emphasising the voices of
others. A truly full and fair discussion of public affairs may actually
require government intervention.
If the High Court had been convinced
by these arguments, it may have placed less emphasis on the “vigor”
and “variety”
of debate and been more concerned about, say, the
accuracy and fairness of the debate. It may then have come to a different
assessment
of the magnitude of danger posed by regulation of communication in
Theophanous. The Court could perhaps have taken the view that the evils
of false information were not outweighed by the need for free speech.
Reflecting the view of those who have argued for the use of regulation to
enhance political debate, the Court may have concluded
that the existing law of
defamation actually benefited public debate by encouraging accurate reporting in
the first place.[93]
So, even though the freedom of political communication is designed to promote
democracy, the High Court could have adopted a vision
of how that goal is to be
achieved which is different from the Supreme Court’s approach.
In
summary then, the High Court rather quickly allied itself with a philosophical
tradition based on suspicion of government, a
choice which does not necessarily
follow from its identification of the freedom of political communication with
representative government.
My point here is not to argue that the High Court
was actually wrong. The tradition which influences it may well be worthy of
emulation.
My point is much more modest. There are serious competing visions
of freedom of speech and to make a choice between them at this
point is a
relatively risky enterprise which should be avoided where possible.
This
last point explains why my argument is addressed to Theophanous and
Stephens rather than earlier decisions on the
freedom of political communication. Although the adoption of the
free speech philosophy I have criticised began in Australian Capital
Television and Nationwide News, the extension in Theophanous
and Stephens is particularly problematic given that it could have
been avoided by turning to the common law. Before explaining how the common
law
avoids the problems posed by the adoption of a philosophical perspective on the
freedom of political communication, I want to
explore other aspects of the
Theophanous decision which give cause for concern.
The
Theophanous Rule: The Lessons of New York Times v Sullivan
Even if
one accepts the underlying philosophy of the freedom of political discussion,
the practical effect and subsequent development
of these cases might give rise
to concern.
The history of New York Times v Sullivan
suggests how the future development of the Theophanous rule might
encounter difficulties. The New York Times rule has been widely
recognised as seriously problematic even by those sympathetic to the Supreme
Court’s desire to protect
public discourse from the “chilling
effect” of libel
action.[94] Part of
the criticism is that the Court has extended the doctrine too far beyond the
political context.[95]
But even in its original formulation, the rule contains some serious flaws.
Litigation under the rule has proved complex and expensive.
The focus the
New York Times test places on the motives of journalists has placed
reporters and editors under intense scrutiny. They are frequently subject to
intrusive discovery proceedings and pressure to reveal their sources, in order
to establish that they did not act with “actual
malice”.[96]
Further, the focus on the defendants’ motives has been blamed for high
awards of damages against media
defendants.[97]
Critics have claimed that the prospect of such intrusion and a high damages
award creates just the kind of chilling effect that New York
Times was designed to
prevent.[98]
As
New York Times shows then, judicially formulated rules may have
unexpected consequences. There is first, the possibility that the deciding
court
may not foresee the practical effects of the rules it formulates and
second, the unpredictability that follows the subsequent interpretation
of
rules. So, in the case of New York Times v Sullivan, we see both the
overextension of the rule in subsequent decisions and unexpected consequences of
the rule even in its original formulation.
In Theophanous, the
High Court was more able than the New York Times Court to assess the
practical result of the rule precisely because it had the benefit of
the New York Times experience. The High Court rejected the American
decisions extending the notion of “a public figure” beyond public
officials
and candidates for public
office[99] and,
concerned that New York Times’ “actual malice” standard
combined with the requirement that the plaintiff make out a case with
“convincing clarity”
afforded insufficient protection for
reputation,[100] the
High Court reversed the onus of proof and substituted the
“reasonableness” test for the “actual malice”
standard.[101]
However, this reformulation of the New York Times v Sullivan rule opens
the way for the second kind of problem, those which result from subsequent
judicial interpretation. A striking feature
of the test is that it employs the
open standards of “recklessness” and “reasonableness”.
To recall, the
protection depends on the defendant establishing that the
material was not published “recklessly” and that it was
“reasonable
in the
circumstances”.[102]
The broadly formulated terms of the new rule left much discretion in the hands
of the courts who were to apply and develop it. Although
not unheard of, the
standard embodied in the recklessness and reasonableness requirements would have
to be defined in the context
of the freedom of political communication by the
courts. The notion of a “reasonable” publication was particularly
unclear.
One important outstanding issue was whether this required that the
defendant establish an honest belief in the truth of the matter
published.[103] The
little clarification given by the Court raised further questions. Although the
Court indicated that “[t]he publisher should
be required to show that, in
the circumstances which prevailed, it acted reasonably, either by taking some
steps to check the accuracy
of the impugned material or by establishing that it
was otherwise justified in publishing without taking such
steps”,[104]
it was not at all clear what kinds of steps are necessary or when a publisher is
justified in disregarding them. These judgments
were for later development,
principally by the lower courts.
The test’s novelty also leaves other
important issues undecided. Even during the short time in which Theophanous
stood unaltered, lower courts had to decide matters not clearly addressed by
the High Court but which nevertheless may have a profound
effect on the ultimate
operation of the rule, namely its application to defamatory
comment[105] and
whether the test was for the judge or the
jury.[106]
Of
course, there is too little evidence to conclude that the Theophanous
rule failed. The rule might ultimately have succeeded in striking an
appropriate balance between the protection of reputation and
freedom of
communication. My point again is modest. The New York
Times experience shows that there is a substantial risk of the rule not
achieving its aims and that risk, as I shall now explain, can be
minimised by
adopting the common law alternative.
Risk and the Common Law
My
suggestion that a common law solution in Theophanous and Stephens
might have allowed the High Court to avoid these risks, is obviously based
on a greater confidence in common law reasoning. There
are two bases for this
confidence.
The Stakes of a Decision: Top Down and Bottom Up
Reasoning
One feature of the freedom of speech cases, including
Theophanous and Stephens, which I have suggested is particularly
troubling is that they committed the Court to a particular understanding of
freedom of speech.
In doing so, the High Court has engaged in what Judge Posner
has described as “top down”
reasoning.[107] That
is, the High Court has adopted a theory, in this case a theory that the
Australian Constitution limits the power of laws to interfere with
representative government, and it then has approached individual cases by
reference to
this
idea.[108]
The
problem with “top down” reasoning is that it involves an ambitious
statement about an underlying principle. The stakes
of a single decision are
therefore high. This is exemplified by the High Court’s vision of freedom
of political communication
in Theophanous and Stephens. By
contrast, common law reasoning can be unambitious in the level of justification
it advances for a particular decision. A hallmark
of common law reasoning is
that law is made through the adjudication of individual disputes. The
proposition for which a case is
taken to stand is determined by a later court
which then applies, distinguishes, develops or (if the later court is a superior
court)
overrules. In counter-point to top down reasoning, development of a rule
by determination of individual disputes is reasoning from
the bottom
up.
Bottom Up Reasoning in Stephens
The “bottom up”
nature of common law reasoning can be seen in the discussion of the common law
of qualified privilege
by Justices Brennan and McHugh in Stephens.
As
I have said, both these judges developed that doctrine to provide greater
protection to political communication. In doing so, they
relied principally on
extensions of decided cases. Although Justice Brennan upheld the traditional
rule denying protection to publications
to the world at large, as it related to
the publication by a newspaper of its own defamatory
allegation,[109] he
held that where a newspaper publishes a report containing a statement by a third
party, standards are different. Relying on cases
extending qualified privilege
to reports of the proceedings of Parliament, the courts and some other public
bodies,[110] he
concluded that “[i]n principle, an occasion of qualified privilege may
arise where there is a need to inform the public
in order to allow the public to
perform its own proper functions as perceived in the ‘varying conditions
of
society.’”[111]
This required the defence of qualified privilege to respond to the
recognition in earlier freedom of political communication cases that the public
interest includes “the
discussion and formulation of judgments relating to
government, government institutions and political
matters.”[112]
Subject to some
limitations[113]
therefore, he held that an occasion of qualified privilege may arise in
relation to the discussion of such matters even where they
are published to the
world at large.
In extending the common law of qualified
privilege,[114]
Justice McHugh also relied on cases in which the privilege had already been
extended to publications to the world at large. He relied
on the extension of
the privilege to publications in newspapers made in reply to attacks on the
plaintiff or some other
person[115] and even
to publications not in reply to such an
attack.[116] It was,
Justice McHugh concluded, a narrow reading of the occasions on which a person
has an interest or duty to publish material
to the general public which had so
far denied the protection of qualified privilege to most publications in
newspapers.[117]
Like Justice Brennan, he concluded that the privilege was available in principle
if the requisite public interest could be identified.
He then extended the
notion of public interest. Having noted the importance of open debate about
public officials, he concluded:
It is now appropriate for the common law to declare that it is for the “common convenience and welfare” of Australian society that the existing categories of qualified privilege be extended to protect communications made to the general public by persons with special knowledge concerning the exercise of public functions or powers or the performance of their duties by public representatives or officials invested with those functions and powers.[118]
Conceptual Ascent?
Not all scholars agree that this form of
decision making avoids the enunciation of underlying principle which I have
identified as
a troubling feature of Theophanous and Stephens. It
has been argued that “bottom up” reasoning is ultimately theory
laden. Judge Posner advances this argument:
[T]here isn’t much to bottom-up reasoning. We don’t ever really “start” from a mass of cases or from a statute or from a clause of the Constitution. To read a case, to read a statute, a rule, or a constitutional clause presupposes a vast linguistic, cultural, and conceptual apparatus . . . And if, as is so common, the case or statute or other enactment is unclear, and maybe even when it seems quite clear, the reader, to extract or more precisely to impute its meaning, must interpret it; and interpretation, we now know, is as much creation as discovery. [119]
It is certainly true that one method of legal reasoning is the discernment of
principle underlying a series of individual
decision,[120] and
that future cases may then be determined by reference to such an underlying
principle.[121]
Indeed, it has been argued that the very process of drawing an analogy, a
classic “bottom up” style of legal reasoning,
requires some kind of
theory to determine whether one case is relevantly “like”
another.[122] To
some extent, these cases bear how common law reasoning might be underscored by a
more general idea. After all, Justices Brennan
and McHugh did not just assert
that the discussion of political matters was “like” other occasions
of qualified privilege.
They identified that each case concerned a matter of
“public interest” and then extended the notion of public interest
to
political discussion.
However, distinctive features of “bottom
up” reasoning remain and are illustrated by the judgments of Justices
Brennan
and McHugh. Although the common law of qualified privilege is clearly
founded on the notion of “public interest”, that
notion is
undefined. There is perceived to be a “public interest that persons
should be allowed to speak freely on occasions
when it is their duty to speak .
. . in the protection of some (self or) common
interest.”[123]
The general emphasis is on the public rather than the individual
good,[124] but the
parameters of this concept are set not by some overriding theory of the purpose
it is to serve, but through incremental extension
of individual cases. Indeed,
the cases reiterate that the decision will be made on the facts of a particular
case.[125]
The
vagueness of the overriding principle and the comparative specificity with which
applicable factual circumstances are identified
is seen in both judgments.
Justice Brennan stressed that the broad and flexible nature of the principle
underlying qualified privilege
required close attention to the facts of
individual
cases.[126] He
quoted Justice
Dixon:[127]
Whatever advantages may be found in ‘broad’ or ‘flexible’ categories or tests of responsibility or immunity, they are not felt by a judge who wants to be guided in his decision. But the very width of the principles governing qualified privilege for defamation makes it more necessary, in deciding how they apply, to make a close scrutiny of the circumstances of the case, of the situation of the parties, of the relations of all concerned and of the events leading up to and surrounding the publication.
Justice Brennan does just this, reviewing decided cases to determine the
kinds of circumstances in which the privilege has been
extended.[128]
Although
Justice McHugh similarly relied on the importance of open discussion of public
affairs,[129] he
also continued to express the underlying concern of the common law in very
general terms. It is a concern for “the quality
of life and the freedom
of the ordinary individual” which he identifies as “highly dependent
on the exercise of functions
and powers vested in public representatives and
officials”[130]
which justifies the extent of the privilege. Again, the focus of his decision
is to identify the factual circumstances in which
the public interest arises
rather than its philosophical explanation.
These judgments form what
Professor Sunstein has called an “incompletely theorized
agreement”.[131]
That is, an agreement which does not contain a complete account of the theory or
principle which justifies it. Justices Brennan
and McHugh can identify a
particular outcome (that qualified privilege ought to attach to newspaper
reports of matters concerning
public or government affairs) and although they
state a general principle that justifies it (that the discussion of these
matters
is within the public interest), they do not provide a fully articulated
theory of the public interest. The result is that these
Justices are not
required to explain, and have not committed the Court to, a particular
understanding of the value of freedom of
expression. Although a theory, or
theories may emerge over time, this decision forms only a step toward the
formation of that theory.
This, I suggest, avoids the risk that attends an
ambitious decision which formulates a theory of freedom of political
communication.
Development of the Rule
The common law also
helps to avoid the second kind of problem which attends the New York Times v
Sullivan rule, that which arises with the practical application and
subsequent extension of the rule.
The Practical Effects of the Common Law
are Known
First, by building on an established system of law, the Court
is less likely to be taken unawares by the results of its decisions.
After
Theophanous, a judge who adopted Justice McHugh’s or Justice
Brennan’s position would approach a false and allegedly libellous
statement
concerning a public figure with the established standard for qualified
privilege: that there exists between the speaker and listener
the requisite duty
to communicate, and interest in the
communication.[132]
Justices Brennan and McHugh have made only an incremental extension of that
test. Under Justice McHugh’s approach, for example,
a lower court judge
now knows that “communications made to the general public by persons with
special knowledge concerning
the exercise of public functions or powers or the
performance of their duties by public representatives or officials invested with
those functions and
powers”[133]
satisfy the reciprocity of duty and interest test. In other respects, the rule
remains intact and its elements are defined by the
case law.
Given its
long history, the practical operation of the common law is easier to assess.
The High Court can avail itself of critical
analysis and respond accordingly.
Of course, the critical analysis of the common law may be inadequate or the
Court may not fully
avail itself of it. The common law, moreover, may also not
produce a perfect result. Nevertheless, an unexpected, self
defeating result, the failure of a rule to achieve its own aims, that
followed New York Times is less likely if the Court builds on an existing
body of common law instead of formulating a constitutional standard.
Interpretive Resources of the Common Law
A second feature of the
common law is that the body of decided cases provides an interpretive basis for
the development of the law.
These interpretive resources make the second kind
of problem seen with the New York Times rule, overextension by lower
courts, less likely. The underlying case law assists both in formulating a more
precise rule and in the
application of that rule. This is important because the
terms in which the common law is framed might otherwise not seem to have
much
more content than the constitutional rule. The common law concepts of
“special interest”, “exercise of a
public function” and
“public interest” which appear in Justice McHugh’s formulation
of the rule,[134]
for example, might seem equally as malleable as the recklessness and
reasonableness requirements of the majority’s constitutional
approach.
An illustration of the importance of underlying case law is found
in Justice McHugh’s consideration of the protection of comment.
Justice
McHugh was able to determine the application of the extended form of qualified
privilege i.e., that which applies to publication
to the world at large, with
some precision. Justice McHugh declined to extend the defence to the protection
of “bare defamatory
comment”; that is, comment published without the
facts on which it is based. In drawing this limit, he noted that the defence
of
fair comment already protected comment, including bare defamatory comment, on
matters of public interest so long as the factual
basis could be
proved.[135] The
only question, then, was whether the extended form of the privilege should
protect bare defamatory comment based on false assertions of fact. The
protection of comment based on false factual information could be justified
where those facts were published
with the comment since “experience has
shown that, in the absence of malice, the factual content of such publication is
generally
true” and consequently “[s]ociety benefits even though
some statements made on those occasions are in fact
untrue”.[136]
However, because Justice McHugh was not convinced of any additional benefit in
protecting bare defamatory comment based on false
information, it remained
unprotected.[137]
Of
course, Justice McHugh’s determination that the new defence of qualified
privilege did not extend to bare defamatory comment
was based on his own
assessment of the value of false
information.[138]
However, the existing law’s emphasis on the truth of the facts underlying
comment guided his inquiry. He accepted the existing
law and sought a reason to
extend the privilege to comment based on false factual information. That reason
could be found with respect
to comment generally, but not with respect to bare
defamatory comment. So, I do not mean to deny an element of choice in the
interpretation
of the common
law.[139] I rely on
the relatively modest point that the common law guides, but of course, does not
determine the development of the rule.
The result, nonetheless, is that the
ultimate direction of the rule is likely to be more easily apparent at the time
of its formulation
and its development by lower courts less likely to take it in
unexpected and unfortunate directions.
Justice McHugh’s approach to the
matter of comment is to be contrasted with the Supreme Court of South
Australia’s position
in Peterson v Advertiser Newspapers
Ltd.[140] That
Court held that the “reasonableness” requirement of the
Theophanous rule applied to comment as well as to statements of fact,
rejecting the argument that the “reasonableness” requirement
was
difficult to apply to material that does not include factual
assertions.[141]
However, the Court had far less authority on which to rely. Although Justice
Olsson considered and distinguished some American case
law[142] much of the
decision was based on the High Court’s failure to draw any such
distinction and its apparent inclusion of comment
in its observations about the
coverage of the
rule.[143] Rather
than considering the overall operation of and justification for a well developed
body of law, as Justice McHugh did, the Court
was reduced to examining a single
High Court decision for clues. The Supreme Court’s ultimate decision may
or may not have
been right. The important point is that in dealing with a new
constitutional standard, courts have little precedential guidance
and unguided
lower courts have more scope to overextend a doctrine.
The Interpretive
Resources of the Common Law and Constitutional Analysis
Before
continuing, I want to address one possible objection to this argument. It might
be argued that the resources of the common
law are available to the
constitutional decision maker who chooses to incorporate common law standards
into constitutional analysis.
That is, if we consider that the common law is
likely to provide us with greater wisdom in relation to matters with which it
has
long dealt, then the best solution is to incorporate the wisdom of the
common law into the interpretation of the Constitution. This would reduce my
argument to a claim that the Court ought to rely on the guidance of the common
law in formulating constitutional
standards.
In reply to this, it must
first be said that this argument does not address one justification for common
law preference, the desirability
of leaving open legislative and executive
action, at all. However, because my argument principally relies on other
benefits of common
law reasoning, there is some undeniable force to this
objection. It is true that the common law can inform the constitutional decision
maker as well as the common law judge. Indeed, this is very close to the
approach which the Supreme Court of South Australia took
in Peterson to
the interpretation of the “reasonableness” requirement of the
Theophanous rule. In applying the rule, Justices Olsson and Mullighan
took the view that the High Court intended to adopt the standard of
reasonableness
developed under s 22 of the Defamation Act 1974
(NSW).[144]
Consequently, they interpreted the requirement by reference to the authorities
interpreting that
section.[145] Far
from beginning with a clean slate therefore, they had the interpretive resources
of those cases. In a similar manner, a court
could incorporate a common law
standard and avail itself of the greater understanding of the practical effect
of its ruling and
the more certain basis for the elaboration of a
rule.
However, there is a limit to what this method can achieve in terms of
my argument. Before incorporating a standard developed by the
common law, or as
in Peterson, through the interpretation of a statute, a judge would have
to decide that the common law standard was an appropriate guide for the
development of constitutional doctrine. In cases like the freedom of political
communication, where the development of constitutional
doctrine is governed by
an overarching theory, the incorporation of a common law standard brings with it
some elaboration of that
theory. If therefore, the Supreme Court of South
Australia was correct, and the High Court intended to incorporate the
reasonableness
requirement of s 22, then the High Court was making an important
statement about the nature of the freedom of political communication. The cases
elaborating
the s 22 requirement are generally very protective of reputation.
The following passage from Austin v Mirror Newspapers Limited is
indicative of the general approach:
A newspaper with a wide circulation that publishes defamatory comments on untrue facts will in the ordinary course of events have no light task to satisfy a judge that it was reasonable to do so. Those in public life must have broad backs and be prepared to accept harsh criticism but they are at least entitled to expect that care should be taken to check that the facts upon which such criticism is based are true. [146]
The adoption of this standard into constitutional analysis appears to imply
that this standard is appropriate for the purposes of
representative democracy.
The Supreme Court of South Australia does not make the implications of its
analysis for the freedom of political communication
explicit.[147]
However, any sustained analysis of this would have to justify it in terms of the
theory which governs the freedom of political communication.
The question for a
court would be how such protection fits the notion of representative government
which underlies the freedom of
political
communication.[148]
Consequently, as long as the freedom of political communication is interpreted
by reference to the principle of representative government,
then the
incorporation of the common law is likely to involve just the kind of decision
making which I have suggested should be avoided.
IV LIMITS AND OBJECTIONS
The Limit of this Approach
Although I have
argued that Theophanous and Stephens were cases in which the
common law was an appropriate alternative to constitutional decision making, I
do not want to suggest that
the Court should automatically prefer a common law
solution. The approach I have advocated ought to be seen as an appropriate
strategy
for the High Court in some cases.
Most obviously, common law
preference is less likely to be appropriate when constitutional reasoning can
proceed without the elaboration
of an important overarching theory as is the
case, for example, where constitutional interpretation relies primarily on
construction
of the
text[149] or the
interpretation of precedent. In the latter case in particular, constitutional
decision making is much like the common law,
depending on analogical reasoning
from case to case and the gradual construction of principle over
time.[150]
Therefore,
there may be cases in which constitutional reasoning can proceed in an
incremental “bottom up” fashion in much
the same way as, and
consequently with many of the advantages of, the common law. These may well be
cases in which common law preference
brings few of the advantages I have
identified. For the moment, however, it is sufficient to say that
Theophanous and Stephens were not such cases. Those cases relied
upon a doctrine that went beyond straightforward interpretation of the text or
extrapolation
from decided cases. Instead, the High Court relied upon the
structure of representative government created by the Constitution and
determined that a level of political communication is necessary to assure its
effective
operation.[151] I do
not mean to suggest that the arguments are without foundation or are an
illegitimate form of constitutional
argument.[152]
However, they require a court to interpret principle abstracted from the
Constitution and consequently will involve the elaboration of the concept
involved in that principle. This is the kind of reasoning I have suggested
that
the High Court should avoid where there is a more secure basis for its
decision, in the form of the common law.
Objections to this Approach
The need for a clear articulation
of the constitutional standard
Perhaps the strongest argument against
my position is that the High Court’s role requires it to decide, not
avoid, important
constitutional matters. Harry Kalven’s famous analysis of
New York Times v Sullivan suggests this point. Kalven powerfully argued
that an important virtue of New York Times v Sullivan is that the Supreme
Court looked beyond the narrowest possible formulation of the issue and took the
opportunity to address the important
values underlying the First
Amendment.[153]
Kalven pointed out that the Supreme Court could have decided the case solely on
the basis that there was insufficient evidence to
connect the plaintiff to the
statements made in the advertisements in
question.[154]
Instead, with a “hitherto rarely displayed . . . taste for common
sense”,[155]
the Court proceeded to address the long unsettled issue of seditious libel. It
declared as the “central meaning of the Amendment”
that seditious
libel cannot be made the subject of government sanction. This was then applied
to defamation[156]
but the importance of the decision lies in “the generous sweep of the
major premise and not the application of it to the point
of defamation law
involved in the Times
case.”[157]
Kalven’s point is that the Supreme Court’s role may require it
to do more than decide a case. As the final expositor
of the Constitution, it
ought to articulate important
standards.[158]
Part of the importance of such a role is the guidance that such decisions give
to lower courts, legislators and
litigants.[159] A
further argument might place particular emphasis on the nature of freedom of
speech. The argument might be that where very important
values like freedom of
speech are concerned, there is a need for clear statements of those values. One
argument about First Amendment
doctrine is that it ought to be developed so that
it will withstand pressure during periods of strong intolerance for unorthodox
ideas.[160] A
doctrine formed by the drawing of analogies based on an unarticulated and partly
formed theory might lack the intuitive appeal
to command popular support and
give judges, who are themselves susceptible to the intolerance of the times, too
much discretion.
There are several responses to these criticisms. First,
these arguments do not apply with such great force where the method of
constitutional
avoidance is common law decision making. The common law is
somewhat better equipped to fulfil the need for statements of important
principle than other methods of constitutional avoidance. Kalven pointed out
that if New York Times v Sullivan had been decided on the narrow basis
that there was insufficient evidence connecting the defendants to the
publication in question,
it would still have had some value in elucidating free
speech principles. It would have indicated that “[i]f such connection
is
too easily made, all criticism of government policy, however impersonal will
carry implicit defamation of whatever officials were
in charge of the policy
attacked.”[161]
But as Kalven clearly appreciated, this value is not comparable with the broad
and important discussion in New York Times. Like most alternative
grounds of decision it would carry its message by implication rather than
direct enunciation of principle.
Consider by contrast Justice McHugh’s
decision in Stephens expanding the common law concept of “public
interest”. Although building on the common law of qualified privilege, he
is able to make quite clear the importance of open discussion of public issues:
In the last decade of the twentieth century, the quality of life and the freedom of the ordinary individual in Australia are highly dependent on the exercise of functions and powers vested in public representatives and officials by a vast legal and bureaucratic apparatus funded by public moneys. How, when, why and where those functions and powers are or are not exercised are matters that are of real and legitimate interest to every member of the community. Information concerning the exercise of those functions and powers is of vital concern to the community[162]
Of course, I have argued that one of the virtues of this decision is that it
is expressed rather vaguely and its limits are determined
principally by
reference to specific factual
circumstances.[163]
Nevertheless, it must be seen that this passage is closer to New
York Times, than a judgement which avoided an issue by reference
to a concept such as standing or by the narrow interpretation of a statute.
So,
a decision on the common law is rather more like the kind of enunciation of
principle than some other methods of constitutional
avoidance. At the same
time, it leaves some important decision making until later, a feature which I
have argued is desirable.
Second, in so far as the argument against my
position is based on the need to create stable constitutional norms about
freedom of
speech, it is not clear that the argument would counsel against an
initial period of common law preference. The argument for the
formulation of
rules that are resistant to the pressure of intolerant times, was made in the
context of the comparatively well developed
law of the First
Amendment.[164] In
the context of a developing law of freedom of speech, it may be that
the need for stable constitutional rules protecting freedom of speech is best
served by
a slow evolution of standards which then have the capacity to endure.
The fate of the Theophanous rule perhaps supports this view. The
adventurousness of Theophanous made it fragile and the radical
reformulation of the doctrine three years later in Lange hardly
contributed to stable constitutional norms governing speech
protection.
Finally, there is a more general point which applies to each of
these arguments. The avoidance of statement of important principle
with its
consequent risk is sometimes more important than the enunciation of principle.
I think that this is particularly likely
to be the case where, as in
Theophanous and Stephens, an important doctrine is in its early
stages of development. Theophanous and Stephens, should be
contrasted in this regard to New York Times v Sullivan. At the time of
New York Times, the First Amendment had been the subject of far greater
development by the courts than the freedom of political communication has
yet
received in Australia. What is more, there had been a long running controversy
over the constitutionality of seditious libel
which the Supreme Court put to
rest in New York Times. The case therefore occurred in the context of a
relatively mature body of law and in the face of an enduring controversy. This
was far from the position in Australia when Theophanous and
Stephens were decided. So, while there might be cases in which
even the principled development of the common law seems insufficient, having
regard to the
important role of the High Court, I venture to suggest that
Theophanous and Stephens were not such cases.
Failure to
avoid the Constitutional Issue and Loss of Candour in Constitutional
Decision Making
A further argument against my position might be drawn from arguments made
against advocacy of constitutional avoidance through statutory
interpretation.
That argument is that expedient avoidance of constitutional decision making
obscures the real ground of
decision.[165] This
has two results. First, there is a lack of candour in judicial decision
making. Moreover, it means that constitutional avoidance does not
achieve what it claims: it does not really allow a court to avoid a
constitutional
decision because embedded in a decision to prefer a common law
solution, is a preliminary judgment about the constitutional issue.
Professor
Schauer made this argument in the course of his critique of the rule, enunciated
in
Ashwander,[166]
that where fairly possible, a court should interpret a statute to be consistent
with the Constitution. As Schauer points out, this rule is only important where
a court perceives that the statute could be read as unconstitutional.
If there
is no potential for conflict, then the court can simply interpret the statute
without the need to call on the Ashwander
rule.[167]
Consequently, resort to statutory interpretation to avoid constitutional
decision making carries with it the message that the court
has real
constitutional doubts.
The same could be said of constitutional avoidance
through use of the common law. The argument would be that there will only be a
need to resort to the common law when judges conclude that there is a possible
constitutional argument, but one which requires an
ambitious level of
justification. If a judge is convinced that no possible constitutional
argument existed, as were Justices Brennan
and McHugh in Theophanous,
then the common law is not an avoidance technique. So if the majority in
Theophanous had employed the approach I am suggesting, we would still
have some idea about their constitutional views. It would be a safe assumption
that they disagreed with Justices Brennan and McHugh that the implied freedom of
political communication had no operation in relation
to defamation actions by
public officials. On the contrary, it would appear that they considered it
possible that the freedom of
political communication had such an effect but were
not prepared to engage in the kind of decision making that would explain its
basis.
There is some undeniable force to this argument. The prudential use of
the common law to avoid constitutional decision making inevitably
involves
leaving constitutional concerns unarticulated. Indeed, that is part of its
virtue. Rather than undermining my argument
that constitutional avoidance brings
with it some benefits, however, this argument merely points to a cost it incurs.
The question
therefore remains whether the benefits I have identified outweigh
these costs. This point can be answered by repeating my argument
that the costs
of avoidance are worth it. At least in the kinds of circumstances I have
described, avoidance even with its costs
is preferable to the formulation of
rules whose ultimate operation is uncertain and potentially self-defeating.
Corruption of the Common Law
The final counter-argument I
will address is also drawn from arguments made against constitutional avoidance
through statutory interpretation.
However, it is rather easier to dismiss.
One point made about constitutional avoidance through statutory
interpretation is that it distorts principles that have their own
value and
hence undermines their capacity to achieve those aims. Gunther makes the point
in relation to the avoidance of constitutional
decision making through statutory
interpretation, arguing that “[a] vital Court task, after all, is the
interpretation of legislation
in contexts free from ulterior purposes of
avoidance.”[168]
Schauer makes the argument slightly more forcefully. His point is that the
avoidance principle tends to lead courts away from an
interpretation they would
otherwise prefer. There will rarely, if ever, be a case in which a
constitutional interpretation and a
non-constitutional interpretation of a
statute will be equally plausible since the process of interpretation is likely
to produce
a preferred result. If that result is unconstitutional, then
preferring a constitutional reading in order to avoid constitutional
decision
making draws the Court away from the more natural reading of the
legislation. So, the result is a distortion of statutory interpretation
and the loss of the value we place on courts giving their preferred
interpretation.[169]
It
is tempting to make the same argument about the common law. In the same manner,
it might be said that the principle of constitutional
avoidance through
interpretation of the common law only comes into play when the interpretation
which the courts might otherwise
give the common law raises some constitutional
doubt. The principle therefore has the potential to lead courts to develop the
common
law in a particular manner precisely to avoid conflict with the
Constitution, perhaps leading to a strained reading of the common
law.
However, unlike the arguments with which I have just dealt, this point
has less relevance where constitutional issues are avoided
through common law
decision making than where statutory interpretation is the alternative basis of
decision. Even if the technique
leads courts to prefer readings of the common
law that are consistent with constitutional principle, it is not clear that this
is
a bad thing. One argument that could be made about the common law is that it
ought to respond to developments in constitutional principle. Indeed,
this would be consistent with Ronald Dworkin’s requirement
of
“integrity in law”, a principle which “instructs judges to
identify legal rights and duties, so far as possible,
on the assumption that
they were all created by a single author - the community personified -
expressing a coherent conception of
justice and
fairness.”[170]
If laws are to express a coherent system of values, cross-fertilisation between
the constitutional doctrine and the common law is
desirable.
V LANGE V THE
AUSTRALIAN BROADCASTING CORPORATION
The decisions in Theophanous and Stephens were short lived. Shortly afterwards, two members of the majority retired and some resistance to the decisions was evident in the High Court.[171] The opportunity to reconsider them arose when David Lange, the former Prime Minister of New Zealand, sued the Australian Broadcasting Corporation in defamation[172] and challenged the correctness of Theophanous and Stephens.[173] The High Court abandoned both the adoption of United States free speech jurisprudence and the particular test that I have criticised. However, as I will show, its response is only partially consistent with the approach I have recommended.
The Decision
The High Court responded to the challenge to
Theophanous and Stephens with a rare unanimous decision. It
upheld the position that the freedom of political communication operated to
limit defamation actions
brought in relation to political discussion. However,
it abandoned the constitutional standard enunciated in Theophanous and
replaced it with an approach which shows greater deference to the common law.
Three features of the decision are significant
for my argument.
The
Basis of the Freedom of Political Communication
First, Lange
contains an important restatement of the constitutional basis and nature of the
freedom of political communication. Since the High
Court first recognised the
implied freedom of political communication, there had been divisions within the
Court over its nature.
In particular, some members of the Court had interpreted
the implication of representative democracy narrowly, stressing that the
content
of the implication is to be construed principally by reference to the text. In
McGinty v Western Australian Newspapers, Chief Justice Brennan explained
this
approach:[174]
Although the term “representative democracy” is useful to explain the text on which the implied freedom depends . . . [i]t is logically impermissible to treat “representative democracy” as though it were contained in the Constitution, to attribute to the term a meaning or content derived from sources extrinsic to the Constitution and then to invalidate a law for inconsistency with the meaning or content so attributed. The text of the Constitution can be illuminated by reference to representative democracy but the concept neither alters nor adds to the text.
Much of the criticism of Theophanous and Stephens was
based on a perceived departure from this method of constitutional
interpretation.[175]
Justice McHugh explained his concern that the majority had proceeded “just
as if the Constitution contained a Ch IX with a s 129 which read ‘Subject
to this Constitution, representative democracy is the law of Australia,
notwithstanding any law to the
contrary’”.[176]
Whatever
the merits of the criticism, the narrower, more textually based approach
prevails in Lange. The Court stated:
Since McGinty it has been clear, if it was not clear before, that the Constitution gives effect to the institution of “representative government” only to the extent that the text and structure of the Constitution establish it . . . the relevant question is not, “What is required by representative and responsible government?” It is, “What do the terms and structure of the Constitution prohibit, authorise or require?”[177]
The Court therefore began its consideration of the implied freedom of
political communication with the text and structure of the Constitution. At the
heart of the Court’s analysis are ss. 7 and
24[178] which
“read in context, require the members of the Senate and the House of
Representatives to be directly chosen at periodic
elections by the people of the
states and the Commonwealth
respectively.”[179]
Other elements of representative government are found in the provisions that set
out the relationship between the Executive and the
Parliament, in particular
those which provide for a system of responsible ministerial
government[180] and
also in s. 128, the provision for amendment by popular
referendum.[181]
The
Court’s approach to the freedom of political communication is that it
limits interference with aspects of representative
government that can be
identified in the text. Sections 7 and 24 and related sections give rise to an
implication protecting the representative nature of the Parliament. Thus
communication “which
enables the people to exercise a free and informed
choice as electors” cannot be
restricted.[182] The
sections which give rise to a system of responsible government
“necessarily imply a limitation on legislative and executive
power to deny
the electors and their representatives information concerning the conduct of the
executive branch of government throughout
the life of a federal
Parliament”[183]
and s. 128 requires the protection of information “that might be relevant
to the vote [electors] cast in a referendum to amend the
Constitution.”[184]
The
Common Law and the Constitution – The Relationship
Reconsidered
The second significant feature of Lange is
that the High Court gave more detailed consideration to the relationship
between the common law and the Constitution. As shown above, in
Theophanous, the majority held that the constitutional requirement of
free political communication affected the common
law.[185] The
explanation in the principal majority judgment was rather brief. Rejecting the
argument that the common law was unchanged
by the Constitution because it was a
pre-existing system, the majority stated:
It is . . . clear that the implied freedom is one that shapes and controls the common law. At the very least, development in the common law must accord with its content. And though it may not have been apparent . . . prior to the decisions in Nationwide News and Australian Capital Television, if the content of the freedom so required, the common law must be taken to have adapted to it.[186]
Deane J considered the matter in more detail. He argued that state
laws were subject to the Constitution, relying on covering clause V which
provides that the Constitution “shall be binding on the courts, judges and
people of every State” and on ss 106 and 108 which provide for the
continuation of State laws “subject to this
Constitution”.[187]
He concluded that the implication of freedom of political communication applied
to state laws “statutory or inherited”,
thus apparently including
the common law.
In Lange, however, a different explanation
emerged. First, the High Court took the view, as Brennan J had in his
Theophanous dissent, that the Constitution was primarily addressed to
legislative and executive
action.[188] This
would appear to preclude a rule of the kind enunciated in Theophanous
which provided a constitutional defence to a common law claim. But despite
this, the common law does not escape constitutional
scrutiny. The High Court
held that “the Constitution, the federal, State and territorial laws, and
the common law in Australia together constitute the law of this country and form
‘one
system of
jurisprudence’”.[189]
Further, it held that “[w]ithin that single system, the basic law of the
Constitution provides the authority for the enactment of valid statute law and
may have effect on the content of the common
law.”[190]
Thus, despite their analysis that the Constitution was addressed to legislative
and executive action, the Court held that the common law must conform to the
Constitution. Consequently, although they departed from the
“constitutional defence” enunciated in Theophanous, as we
shall see, the Court altered the common law to conform to constitutional
requirements.
The New Test in Lange
Having clarified the
basis of the freedom of political communication and its operation on the common
law, the Court then outlined
a new test which determines whether regulation of
political communication is constitutionally permissible. In this respect, the
decision marks a dramatic shift. Suddenly, the more deferential approach to
review expounded by Justice
Brennan[191] appears
to gain general acceptance. Far from requiring a “compelling
justification” or “pressing social need”,
at least where
regulation targets the content of communication, the Court sets a single
standard according to which a law that burdens
the freedom of communication must
be “reasonably appropriate and adapted to serve a legitimate
end”.[192]
The
High Court then applied this test to the law in question, the defamation law of
New South Wales. The High Court held that the
law of New South Wales did burden
the freedom of communication but that this was appropriately adapted to a
legitimate purpose and
therefore valid. Relevant for my argument is the
Court’s approach to the common law of
defamation.[193] As
a first step, the High Court extended the common law of qualified privilege to
conform to the constitutional requirement. In
a manner similar to that of
Justice McHugh in Stephens, it held that the common law
should recognise that each Australian has an interest in disseminating and
receiving information “concerning
government and political matters that
affect the people of Australia” and a duty to disseminate it as a
corollary.[194] The
High Court then restricted this extension of the privilege by requiring that the
defendant must show that the publication was
reasonable in the circumstances and
allowing for defeat of the defence if the plaintiff could demonstrate that the
publication was
actuated by malice or improper
motive.[195] The
High Court held that the common law of qualified privilege when reformulated in
this way, did not unduly burden the freedom
of political
communication.
Significance for Common Law Preference
For those who
advocate the avoidance of constitutional decision making in review of the common
law, Lange is in one respect disappointing. In reassessing
Theophanous and Stephens, the High Court did not avoid the
constitutional issue. It is true that the Court proceeded by developing the
common law, but by
indicating that the development of the common law was
required by the freedom of political communication, the Court gave a clear
indication of its constitutional views. It held:
Because the Constitution requires ‘the people’ to be able to communicate with each other with respect to matters that could affect their choice in federal elections or constitutional referenda or that could throw light on the performance of ministers of State and the conduct of the executive branch of government, the common law rules concerning privileged communications, as understood before the decision in Theophanous . . . failed to meet that requirement.[196]
Because the constitutional requirement drove the reformulation of the common
law, the new common law test reveals something of the
content of that
requirement.
Nevertheless, other aspects of the decision are generally
sympathetic to my arguments. First, the High Court’s preference for
the
formulation of a common law standard over the enunciation of a new
constitutional standard preserves the understanding of the
practical effects of
the rule and the benefits of greater interpretative resources that, I have
argued, attend common law reasoning.
Consequently, though the Court preserves
the “reasonableness” standard that I have suggested was a
troublingly open ended
feature of the constitutional standard, the future
development of the standard will be guided by existing law. The High
Court’s
own analysis shows this. The High Court included the
reasonableness requirement as a special additional requirement of the extended
form of the common law privilege because the traditional law of qualified
privilege “devised for situations where usually only
one person receives
the publication is unlikely to be appropriate when the publication is to tens of
thousands, or more, of readers,
listeners or viewers”. Because of the
greater damage such publication can do to reputation, it held “a
requirement of
reasonableness as contained in s 22 of the Defamation Act, which
goes beyond mere honesty is properly to be seen as reasonably appropriate and
adapted to the protection of reputation and,
thus, not inconsistent with the
freedom of communication which the Constitution
requires.”[197]
Lower courts therefore know that the requirement exists to give reputation a
higher level of protection than is traditionally provided
by the common law, in
response to the special dangers of mass publication. The level of protection
afforded to reputation by the
common law as it stood before Lange will
provide a starting point from which the new test is to be distinguished in
accordance with the High Court’s rationale
for the extension.
A second
feature sympathetic to my argument is that the precise nature of the
constitutional standard is not highly developed by the
Court. There is no
ambitious or wide ranging justification of the Court’s view that a
particular extension of the common law
is required by the freedom of political
communication. The statement simply is that the privilege must be extended to
meet the Constitution’s requirement that “‘the people’ .
. . be able to communicate with each other with respect to matters that
could
affect their choice in federal elections or constitutional referenda or that
could throw light on the performance of ministers
of State and the conduct of
the executive branch of
government”.[198]
Thus particular circumstances, rather than underlying or overarching theory, are
the focus. This is to be contrasted with the adoption
of the American emphasis
on unregulated debate in Theophanous, which, as I have shown, brings with
it a particular, and contestable, understanding of freedom of
communication.
A Final Objection
Although broadly sympathetic to my
argument, this last feature of Lange raises a final possible objection to
my argument. It must be admitted that Lange avoids the enunciation of a
philosophy of freedom of speech in a different manner from that I have
suggested. By tying the freedom
of political communication closely to specific
provisions of the Constitution, the Justices have rejected the notion that the
Constitution can be interpreted according to a general notion of
“representative democracy’. This is what the Court means by its
statement “the relevant question is not, ‘What is required by
representative and responsible government?’ It is, ‘What
do the
terms and structure of the Constitution prohibit, authorise or
require?’”[199]
Lange might therefore suggest that the appropriate response to the
“top-down” nature of Theophanous and Stephens is not
a preference for the common law, but a return to “bottom up”
constitutional reasoning. This appears to be the
approach advocated by Justice
McHugh who, in McGinty, specifically rejected the notion of
“top-down” constitutional
reasoning.[200]
As
I have already explained, constitutional reasoning can proceed in a manner which
avoids the statement of important underlying principle
and, where the Court does
this, the case for common law preference is much weakened. However, I do not
accept that the possibility
of textually based constitutional reasoning makes
the case for common law preference superfluous. Even if the High Court were
entirely
to abandon argument which takes underlying principle as its starting
point, this view would be problematic. It involves adopting
a theory about
constitutional interpretation that is itself
ambitious.[201]
There are arguments, some of which I have outlined
above,[202] that
counsel the exposition of important underlying principle, in some circumstances.
Therefore, for the kinds of reasons that I
have advocated caution in adopting a
particular understanding of freedom of speech, I would advocate caution in
adopting a theory
of constitutional interpretation. The enterprise is ambitious
and consequently risky. So while the adoption of this more cautious
incremental
style of constitutional interpretation has manifest advantages, the complete
preclusion of other styles of constitutional
interpretation seems premature.
To conclude, the approach I have advocated has one advantage even over the
use of less ambitious styles of constitutional reasoning.
It allows for risky,
ambitious decision making to be avoided at some points without requiring the
Court to determine the important
question of the place of “top down”
argument in constitutional analysis.
VI CONCLUSION: THE COMMON LAW THE
CONSTITUTION AND THE FUTURE
The problem I have considered here will
be of continuing significance as the High Court moves the Constitution into the
traditional domain of the common law. On the horizon may be an overlap between
the constitutional requirements of fairness
of process and traditional common
law concepts. The High Court’s vigorous interpretation of provisions
conferring the judicial
power of the Commonwealth exclusively on courts
designated by Chapter III, has raised the notion of constitutionally required
fairness
of
process.[203]
Further, some Justices have indicated their view that constitutionally required
fairness of process includes the concept of a fair
trial traditionally defined
by the common
law.[204] The
consequence may be that the High Court is faced with an appeal arguing that an
accused was denied both the common law right to
a fair trial and the
requirements of Chapter III. It could therefore proceed by elaborating the
content of a constitutional “fairness
of process” requirement or by
considering the common law concept. Although I will not here suggest a
substantive solution,
the matter should be analysed in the terms I have
outlined. A part of the Court’s inquiry should be to consider what
commitments
a decision on the constitutional notion of fairness of process would
require and how a common law solution might avoid this.
This article was published in the Federal Law Review, Volume 26, Number 2, 1998
*BA (UNSW); LLB (UNSW); LLM (Columbia), Faculty of
Law, Australian National University. This article forms part of the
author’s
JSD dissertation at Columbia University School of Law. The
author wishes to thank Adelle Blackett, Vincent Blasi, Michael Dorf,
Kent
Greenawalt, Christine Haight Farley, Peter Lindseth, William Ryan , Peter
Strauss and George Williams for their comments on
earlier drafts and other
contributions to the development of this article. Theo Varvaressos provided
excellent editorial
assistance.
[1] The
High Court first recognised a constitutional freedom of political communication
in Australian Capital Television v The Commonwealth [1992] HCA 45; (1992) 177 CLR 106
and Nationwide News v Wills [1992] HCA 46; (1992) 177 CLR 1 in which the High Court held
that the system of representative and responsible government established by the
Australian Constitution, impliedly prohibits legislative action that interferes
with the political expression necessary for the proper operation of this
system
of government. Therefore, legislation prohibiting some forms of political
advertising (in Australian Capital Television) and legislation creating
an offence for speech bringing a particular administrative tribunal into
disrepute (in Nationwide News), were declared
invalid.
[2] JA
La Nauze, The Making of the Australian Constitution (1972); AI Clark,
Studies in Australian Constitutional Law (1901) at 358. Consequently, the
constitutions of the two countries share many basic features. The two
constitutions share a popularly
elected House of Representatives, an upper house
which represents (at least in theory) the interests of the states, division of
powers
between the arms of government, the enumeration of federal powers and
similar provisions relating to the judiciary and the exercise
of judicial power.
Sir Anthony Mason, “The Role of a Constitutional Court in a Federation: a
Comparison of the Australian and
United States Experience” (1986) 16
Fed L Rev
1.
[3] It has
assisted in justifying judicial review (Australian Communist Party v
Commonwealth (Communist Party Case)) [1951] HCA 5; (1951) 83 CLR 1 at 262,
citing Marbury v Madison 5 US [1803] USSC 16; (1 Cranch) 137 (1803)); influenced
approaches to interpretation (D’Emden v Pedder [1904] HCA 1; (1904) 1 CLR 91 at
111; O’Sullivan v Noarlunga Meat Ltd [1954] HCA 29; (1954) 92 CLR 565 at 597;
Fairfax v Federal Commissioner of Taxation [1965] HCA 64; (1965) 114 CLR 1 at 7 citing
McCulloch v Maryland 17 US [1819] USSC 5; (4 Wheat) 316 (1819)) and influenced the
development of relationships between the federal government and the states.
(Melbourne Corporation v The Commonwealth [1947] HCA 26; (1947) 74 CLR 31 at 61,
81 , 83; citing New York v United States [1946] USSC 13; 326 US 572 (1946)). See
generally, JA Thomson, "American and Australian Constitutions: Continuing
Adventures in Comparative Constitutional Law" (1997) 30 J Marshall L Rev
627.
[4] It
is well documented that the framers chose not to include a US style Bill of
Rights because of their confidence that the common
law and the democratic
process would be sufficient. Official Record of the Debates of the
Australasian Federal Convention (Melbourne, 8 February 1898), pp 688-90; see
also, Amalgamated Society of Engineers v Adelaide Steamship Co Ltd (Engineers
Case) [1920] HCA 54; (1920) 28 CLR 129 at
151-152.
[5]
[1994] HCA 46; (1994) 182 CLR
104.
[6] [1994] HCA 45; (1994)
182 CLR 211.
[7]
[1964] USSC 40; 376 US 254 (1964), see below, n 28 and accompanying
text.
[8] [1997] HCA 25; (1997)
145 ALR 96.
[9]
Eric Barendt, “Free Speech in Australia: a Comparative
Perspective” [1994] SydLawRw 13; (1995) 16 Syd L Rev 149 at 165; Gerald Rosenberg and
John M Williams, “Do not Go Gently into that Good Right: The First
Amendment in the High Court
of Australia” (1997) Sup Ct Rev
439.
[10] See,
below n 28 and accompanying text. The Court was divided and among the three
dissenters who found no constitutional rule akin
to New York Times v
Sullivan, two justices addressed the protection of freedom of speech through
the development of the common law. See below n
37.
[11] The
provision also allows for the review by the High Court of the decision of
“any other court of any State from which at the
establishment of the
Commonwealth an appeal lies to the Queen in
Council”.
[12]
As is well known to American lawyers, in Erie RR v Tompkins [1938] USSC 94; 304 US 64
(1938), the Supreme Court reversed Swift v Tyson 41 US [1817] USSC 12; (16 Peters) 1
(1842) which for almost a hundred years had allowed the development of a
“general common law” by the federal
courts.
[13]
[1938] USSC 94; 304 US 64, 78 (1938) (“Congress has no power to declare substantive rules
of common law applicable in a state whether they be local in
their nature or
‘general’ be they commercial law or a part of the law of torts. And
no clause in the Constitution purports to confer such a power upon the federal
courts.”)
[14]
Michael C Dorf, “Prediction and the Rule of Law” (1995) 42
UCLA L Rev 651 at
695.
[15] There
is, however, some federal common law based on grants of jurisdiction contained
in Article III §2 or in statutes. For
example, the grant of jurisdiction
in Article III § 2 over cases “to which the United States shall be a
party” has
provided the basis for the development of federal law
concerning some obligations of the United States. For a detailed discussion
see, Henry J Friendly, “In Praise of Erie - And of the New Federal Common
Law” (1964) 39 NYU L Rev 383 at 405 -
22.
[16] K.C
Wheare, Federal Government (3rd ed 1953) at 68-69. He goes on to
note that “the United States alone of the four federations we are
discussing [Australia,
Canada, Switzerland and the United States] comes near to
applying this
principle”.
[17]
Official Record of the Debates of the Australasian Federal Convention
(Sydney, 4 March 1891) at
23.
[18] Andrew
Inglis Clark explicitly noted that to confer a general appellate jurisdiction on
the High Court would impose aspects of the
British court structure on a federal
system. He said of the proposal to give the High Court a general appellate
jurisdiction, “I
hope that in addition to a separate federal system of
courts we shall have a court of appeal as the resolution contemplates. That
will be an innovation . . . upon the American system. The American Supreme
Court cannot hear appeals from the supreme courts of
the various states except
in matters of federal law.” Official Record of the Debates of the
Australasian Federal Convention (Sydney, 11 March 1891) at
253.
[19]
Ibid.
[20] For
an account of the controversy surrounding the preservation of the Privy
Council’s role, see, Jack Goldring, The Privy Council and the
Australian Constitution (1996) at 19-33,
44-48.
[21] Sir
John Quick and Sir Robert Garran, The Annotated Constitution of the
Australian Commonwealth (1901) at 725 § 288. In Erie,
the Supreme Court recognised that such uniformity would not be achieved
under Swift because of the persistence of state courts in their own
opinions on questions of common law. [1938] USSC 94; 304 US 64, 74 (1938). The power of the
High Court to review the decision of all state courts avoids the proliferation
of various interpretations
of the common
law.
[22] Ibid.
See also, Official Record of the Debates of the Australasian Federal
Convention (Melbourne, 28 January 1898) at 273,
283.
[23] Quick
and Garran, above n 21. Quick and Garran advanced the same rationale in
support of s 77 of the Australian Constitution, which allows the Parliament to
make laws investing any state court with federal jurisdiction. Although this
was primarily motivated
by a wish to avoid the
“unduly cumbersome
judicial machinery in the early years of the Commonwealth, and only develop and
extend the national judicial
system to meet the gradually increasing
requirements of the people”. Ibid at 803-4, § 337. Quick and Garran
noted that
it is consistent with the “more national and less distinctively
federal” character of the Australian judiciary. They
reiterated the
rationale they advanced for the High Court’s jurisdiction:
“[c]onfidence in the integrity and impartiality
of the Bench prevents any
jealously or distrust of this wide federal jurisdiction; and the same confidence
makes it possible to contemplate
without misgiving the exercise of federal
jurisdiction by State courts”.
Ibid.
[24]
[1994] HCA 46; (1994) 182 CLR
104.
[25]
[1994] HCA 45; (1994) 182 CLR
211.
[26] [1964] USSC 40; 376
US 254
(1964).
[27]
In Stephens, the High Court addressed the additional question of how the
freedom of political communication affected discussion of the political
matters
of a state, and whether a similar implication could be found in the Constitution
of the state of Western Australia. [1994] HCA 45; (1994) 182 CLR 211 at 232-34 per Mason CJ,
Toohey and Gaudron JJ, at 257 per Deane
J.
[28] The
rule in New York Times v Sullivan “prohibits a public official from
recovering damages for a defamatory falsehood relating to his official conduct
unless he
proves that the statement was made with ‘actual malice’ .
. . or with reckless disregard of whether it was false or not.”
[1964] USSC 40; 376 US
254, 279-80 (1964). The Australian rule was formulated slightly differently.
First, Theophanous provides that an action cannot be brought for
publication of false material if (i) the defendant is unaware of the falsity and
not
reckless with regard to its truth and (ii) the publication was reasonable in
all the circumstances. (1994)182 CLR 104 at 140-141.
Second, the onus of proof
is reversed: the defendant must establish, “that it was unaware of
the falsity, that it did not publish recklessly (i.e., not caring whether the
matter
was true or false), and that the publication was reasonable”. Ibid
at 137. Further the rule only applies to public officials
and candidates for
public
office.
[29]
Such as s 41 (a person who acquires the right to vote in a State shall have the
right to vote in the Commonwealth); s 80 (a trial on indictment shall be by
jury); s 116 (Commonwealth shall not make any law "for establishing any
religion, or for imposing any religious observance, or for prohibiting
the free
exercise of any religion ..."); s 117 (States not to discriminate against the
residents of any other states); s 51(xxxi) (acquisition of property to be on
just
terms).
[30]
See generally, Tony Blackshield and George Williams, Australian
Constitutional Law and Theory (2nd ed 1998) at 987-1054. To give an example
of this restrictive reading, the High Court has interpreted the guarantee that a
trial
on indictment shall be by jury, to allow Parliament total freedom in
determining whether the trial shall be by indictment and thus
incur the jury
requirement. R v Bernascone [1915] HCA 13; (1915) 19 CLR 629; R v Archdall &
Roskruge; Ex parte Carrigan & Brown [1928] HCA 18; (1928) 41 CLR
128.
[31] [1994] HCA 46; 182
CLR 104 at 126 per Mason CJ, Toohey and Gaudron JJ, at 164-165 per Deane
J.
[32] The
High Court’s analysis changed in Lange v The Australian Broadcasting
Corporation [1997] HCA 25; (1997) 145 ALR 96. See below nn 171 - 204 and accompanying
text.
[33]
Retail, Wholesale & Department Store Union v Dolphin Delivery Ltd 33
DLR (4th) 174 (1986). See also, McKinney v University of Guelph 76 DLR
(4th) 545 (1990) per La Forest J; K Swinton, “Applications of the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms”, in Walter S Tarnopolsky
and Gerald A
Beaudoin, The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms - Commentary (1982)
at 42. A similar position was taken by Justice Brennan, a dissentient in
Theophanous, with regard to the implied freedom of political
communication. (1994)182 CLR 104 at
153.
[34]
Although in the United States the common law is considered, for the most part,
to be state law, state laws are subject to the provision
of the Bill of Rights,
through the interpretation of the Fourteenth Amendment: Palko v
Connecticut [1937] USSC 174; 302 US 319, 325 (1937). Secondly, although most constitutional
provisions apply to government not private action, judicial enforcement of the
common law constitutes state action: New York Times v Sullivan 3[1869] USSC 146; 76 US
254, 265 (1964). Although, the High Court has reached the same result as the
United States Supreme Court, the precise explanation that
has emerged is
different. It was most clearly expressed in Lange v Australian Broadcasting
Commission where the Court held that “[t]he Constitution, the federal,
State and territorial laws, and the common law in Australia together constitute
the law of this country and form ‘one
system of jurisprudence’ . . .
Within that single system of jurisprudence, the basic law of the Constitution
provides the authority for the enactment of valid statute law and may have
effect on the content of the common law.” (1997) 145 ALJR 96 at
109-10.
[35]
Theophanous [1994] HCA 46; (1994) 182 CLR 104 at 111, 116; Stephens [1994] HCA 45; (1994) 182
CLR 211 at 214, 217.
[36] (1994)182 CLR
104 at 140 per Mason, Toohey and Gaudron JJ, at 187 - 88 per Deane
J.
[37] There
were three dissentients. Justice Brennan dissented on the basis that the
implied freedom operated only to limit the legislative
powers of the Parliament.
[1994] HCA 46; (1994) 182 CLR 104 at 149 Justice Dawson dissented, taking the view he first
expressed in Australian Capital Television and Nationwide News,
that there is no constitutional freedom of political discussion flowing from the
establishment of representative government. Ibid
at 191. Justice McHugh’s
dissent also followed from his decision in Australian Capital Television
and Nationwide News. Although he had joined the majority in striking
down the legislation in those cases, the basis of his decision was considerably
narrower.
He recognised a freedom of political communication only existed to
protect a narrow concept of representative government, the direct
election of
the federal parliament by the people. Consequently, the implied freedom had no
effect on defamation laws. Ibid at 203-
05.
[38] These
cases came to the High Court as cases stated under s 40 of the Judiciary Act
1903 (Cth) which allows for a case raising a constitutional question pending in
a lower court to be removed into the High Court by its
own order. Section 18
then provides for a case to be stated for the Court’s consideration. In
Theophanous and Stephens, the cases were removed to the High Court
under s 40 before their respective trials. Theophanous (1994)182 CLR 104
at 119, Stephens (1994)182 CLR 211 at 235, 258. The Chief Justice stated
a case for the High Court to consider. In Theophanous, the case
consisted of four questions. The first two questions addressed the
constitutional issue. The third question was as follows:
“If yes to any
part or parts of question 1, is any such publication a publication on an
occasion of qualified privilege . .
. ?” (1994)182 CLR 104 at 120.
Strictly, therefore, the question only arose upon a finding that the
Constitutional protection
extended to the publication of material described in
question 1. As they had dissented on this question, Justices Brennan, Dawson
and McHugh took the view that the common law question did not arise. Ibid at
163, 194,
207.
[39] The
classic statement of the defence of qualified privilege is that of Parke B In
Toogood v Spyring (1834)1 C M R 181 at 189: [1834] EngR 363; 149 ER
1044.
[40]
Loveday v Sun Newspapers Ltd [1938] HCA 28; (1938) 59 CLR 503 at
513.
[41]
Morosi v Mirror Newspapers [1977] 2 NSWLR
749.
[42]
Justice Brennan and Justice McHugh both extended the traditional category of
“public interest” to include matters relating
to government and the
conduct of public affairs. (1994)182 CLR 211 at 251 per Brennan J, at 265 per
McHugh J. Further, both Justices
placed emphasis on the status of the maker of
the communication. For Justice Brennan, the privilege will only be available
where
the maker of the communication has “particular knowledge” of
the subject matter, though it will be sufficient if the
publisher had a
reasonable belief that person has such knowledge. Ibid at 252. For Justice
McHugh, the maker of the communication
must have “special
knowledge”. Ibid at 265. The principal differences are that Justice
McHugh extends the privilege
to false statements of fact and comment based on
them, though not to bare defamatory comment whereas Justice Brennan would
require
the statement to be “fair and accurate” and that the subject
of the communication have a reasonable opportunity for response.
Ibid at 252,
267.
[43]
See, below nn 109-18 and accompanying
text.
[44]
Anthony Lewis, Make No Law at 21-22
(1991).
[45]
Ibid at
24-27.
[46]
Ibid at
28-31.
[47]
Ibid at
35.
[48]
See, above n
38.
[49]
See, the questions stated in Theophanous, above n 38. As
the questions reserved in Theophanous dealt with the possible
constitutional and common law bases for protection of the speech in question,
the questions in Stephens simply asked whether the two defences pleaded,
a defence relying on the implied freedom of communication and one relying on
qualified
privilege, were bad in law. Stephens (1994)182 CLR 211 at 231.
No doubt also influenced by the form of the case stated, counsel appear to have
put argument to the High
Court on the basis that the common law of qualified
privilege was a secondary defence, which was to be considered after the
constitutional
question had been decided. Theophanous (1994)182 CLR 104
at 111, Stephens (1994)182 CLR 211 at
214.
[50] Many
of these rules are set out by Justice Brandeis in his famous concurring opinion
in Ashwander v TVA [1960] USSC 29; 297 US 288, 345-49 (1936) (Brandeis J with whom
Stone, Roberts and Cardozo JJ agreed) See generally, Lisa A
Kloppenberg, “Avoiding Constitutional Questions” (1994) 35 BC L
Rev 1003 at 1018 -
1027.
[51]
Ashwander v TVA [1960] USSC 29; 297 US 288, 348 (1936). For instances of the
Australian doctrine of “reading down” statutes and the related
technique of “severance”
whereby the Court may declare parts of a
statute as invalid but allow the rest to stand, see D’Emden v
Pedder [1904] HCA 1; (1904) 1 CLR 91 and R v Commonwealth Court of Conciliation and
Arbitration; Ex parte Whybrow & Co (Bootmaker’s Case No
2)(1910)1 CLR
1.
[52]
Alexander Bickel, The Least Dangerous Branch (2nd ed
1986).
[53] The
Australian Constitution, for example, can only be amended according to the
referendum procedure prescribed by s
128.
[54] The
concern over vulnerability of the United States Supreme Court to political
attack was acute in the aftermath of the Court’s
ultimately futile
resistance to the New Deal. Bickel above n 52, at 45-47, 240. See
generally, Kloppenberg, above n 50 at
1042-1043.
[55]
Kloppenberg, above n 50 1042. On the limited institutional capacity of courts,
see generally, Gerald N Rosenberg, The Hollow Hope
(1991).
[56]
Kloppenberg, above n 50 at
1047.
[57]
Ibid at
1055.
[58]
Ibid at
1040.
[59] This
argument has something in common with and has been influenced by Cass
Sunstein’s recent argument for a strategy of judicial
“minimalism”. That is, a strategy of leaving as much as possible
undecided in cases in which the Court is dealing with
“an issue of high
complexity about which many people feel deeply and on which the nation is in
flux (moral or otherwise).” Cass R Sunstein, “Foreword:
Leaving Things Undecided” (1996) 110 Harv L Rev 4 at 8. Part of
his argument for minimalism is that it reduces “error costs”, the
costs of a wrong
decision.
[60]
Under this standard regulation directed to the content of speech will generally
only be permissible if the government can show that
“its regulation is
necessary to serve a compelling state interest and that it is narrowly drawn to
achieve that end.”
Widmar v Vincent [1981] USSC 227; 454 US 263, 270 (1981). There
are some categories of speech, including obscenity and face to face insults
(often referred to as “fighting
words”) and, subject to New York
Times v Sullivan and related rules, libel which have traditionally been
regarded as subject to a lower standard of review. However, recently the
Supreme
Court has found even regulation of previously “unprotected
categories” of speech will be subject to strict scrutiny unless
it can be
shown to be “content neutral.” RAV v City of St Paul [1992] USSC 99; 505 US
377
(1992).
[61]
Buckley v Valeo [1976] USSC 24; 424 US 1, 48-49 (1976) (“[T]he concept that
government may restrict the speech of some elements of our society in order to
enhance the
relative voice of others is wholly foreign to the First Amendment,
which was designed to secure the widest possible dissemination
of information
from diverse and antagonistic sources, and to assure unfettered interchange of
ideas.” (citations
omitted)).
[62]
[1992] HCA 45; (1992) 177 CLR 106 at 143 per Mason CJ, at 234-35 per McHugh
J.
[63] Ibid at
143 per Mason CJ, at 234-35 per McHugh J. In the case of regulation directed
only at the activity of communication, however,
a less restrictive
proportionality requirement was imposed. That is, the test of
constitutionality depends on whether “the
burden on free communication .
. . is disproportionate to the attainment of the competing public
interest”. Ibid 143 per Mason
CJ. See also, ibid at 235 per McHugh
J.
[64] Like
Chief Justice Mason and Justice McHugh, they set a standard of review which
varies with the nature of the regulation. A law
which aims to control
communication will be more difficult to justify than a law “with respect
to some other subject and whose
effect on such communications is unrelated to
their nature as communications”. Such laws can only be justified if either
they
“do not go beyond what is reasonably necessary for the preservation
of an ordered society or for the protection or vindication
of the legitimate
claims of individuals to live peacefully and with dignity”; or “are
conducive to the overall availability
of the effective means of such
communication in a democratic society.” Nationwide News (1992)177
CLR 1 at 76-77. See also, Australian Capital
Television (1992)177 CLR 106 at 174. Although this standard of review might
appear less stringent than the “compelling justification”
test
advanced by Justices Mason and McHugh, as elaborated by Justice Deane in
Cunliffe v The Commonwealth, the standard is closer to a strict scrutiny
requirement. The requirement that a law must “not go beyond what is
necessary”
means that it must be viewed by a “pressing social
need”. (1993)182 CLR 272 at 339-40 (quoting Lord Goff of Chieveley
in
Attorney-General v Guardian Newspapers Ltd [No.2] [1990] 1 AC 109 at
283-84.)
[65]
Australian Capital Television [1992] HCA 45; (1992) 177 CLR 106 at 157-58. The
remaining member of the majority, Justice Gaudron, took an approach like Justice
Brennan’s. Regulation of
speech is permissible only if it is directed to
the achievement of a legitimate end and “is reasonably and appropriately
adapted
to that end.” Nationwide News [1992] HCA 46; (1992) 177 CLR 1 at
95. See also, Australian Capital Television [1992] HCA 45; (1992) 177
CLR 106 at 218. However, she was also troubled by the provisions allocating
free use of electronic media to some political actors, finding
that the
restrictions placed on political discourse “cannot be viewed as reasonable
and appropriate regulation in a context
where candidates and political parties
are allocated free time for their political advertisements.” Ibid at 221.
The seventh
member of the Court, Justice Dawson, dissented on the basis that the
Constitution included no limitation on legislative power to protect freedom of
political discourse. Ibid at
184.
[66]
Nationwide News [1992] HCA 46; (1992) 177 CLR 1 at
52
[67]
Australian Capital Television [1992] HCA 45; (1992) 177 CLR 106 at 159
citing The Observer and the Guardian v The United Kingdom ([1991] ECHR 49; 1991) 14 EHRR
153 at
178.
[68]
Buckley v Valeo [1976] USSC 24; 424 US 1, 48-49 (1976); see above n
61.
[69] The
legislation restricting political advertising challenged in Australian
Capital Television was designed to improve the political process by reducing
the possibility of corruption and equalising access to the use of electronic
media for political purposes. [1992] HCA 45; (1991) 177 CLR 106 at
130.
[70] Ibid
at 145 per Mason CJ, at 169 per Deane and Toohey
JJ.
[71]
Ibid.
[72]
They were particularly troubled by the provisions for the allocation of free
time which served to mitigate the effect of the regime
in relation to
established political parties, but not in relation to other participants in the
political process. Australian Capital Television (1992)177 CLR 106 at
146, 175,
237.
[73]
Justice Brennan recognised that s 95B (restricting advertising by means of the
electronic media during election periods) was directed
at minimising corruption
and reducing the political advantage which wealth could bring. Ibid at 154-156.
He then held that “[t]he
restrictions imposed by s 95B are comfortably
proportionate to the important objects which it seeks to obtain. The obtaining
of
those objects would go far to ensuring an open and equal democracy. The
openness of political discussion and the equality of the
participants in the
democratic process makes governments responsive to the popular will. The
restrictions on advertising do little
to inhibit the democratic process.”)
Ibid at
161.
[74]
Theophanous [1994] HCA 46; (1994) 182 CLR 104 at 131 per Mason CJ, Toohey and Gaudron
JJ, at 182-83 per Deane
J.
[75]
Alexander Meiklejohn was perhaps the principal exponent of this theory of free
speech. Alexander Meiklejohn, Free Speech and its Relation to Self
Government (1948). See also, Mills v Alabama [1966] USSC 96; 384 US
214, 218 (1966) (“there is practically universal agreement that a major
purpose of [the First Amendment] was to protect the free
discussion of
governmental affairs.”); Buckley v Valeo [1976] USSC 24; 424 US 1, 14 (1976)
(discussion on public issues and debate on the qualifications of candidates is
“an area of the most fundamental
First Amendment activities . . . integral
to the operation of the system of government established by our
Constitution.”). See generally, Frederick Schauer, Free Speech: A
Philosophical Enquiry (1981) at 35-46; Kent Greenawalt, “Free Speech
Justifications” (1989) 89 Colum L Rev 119 at 145 -
146.
[76]
Stromberg v California, [1931] USSC 132; 283 US 359, 369 (1931) (“The
maintenance of the opportunity for free political discussion to the end that
government may be responsive to the
will of the people and that changes may be
obtained by lawful means, an opportunity essential to the security of the
Republic, is
a fundamental principle of our constitutional system.”) See
also, Roth v United States [1957] USSC 100; 354 US 476, 484 (1957); Archibald Cox, The
Court and the Constitution (1987) at 212. (“Only by uninhibited
publication can the flow of information be secured and the people informed
concerning
men, measures, and the conduct of government . . . Only by freedom of
speech, of the press, and of association can people build and
assert political
power, including the power to change the men who govern
them.”)
[77]
[1964] USSC 40; 376 US 254, 269 (1964) citing Roth v United States [1957] USSC 100; 354 US 476, 484
(1957).
[78]
The High Court uses the term “representative democracy” as well as
“representative government”. Theophanous [1994] HCA 46; (1994) 182 CLR 104
at 130, 163. Although some distinction has been drawn between these
concepts, ibid at 199, I use them
interchangeably.
[79]
[1964] USSC 40; 376 US 254, 279
(1964).
[80]
Ibid at
271-72.
[81]
Ibid at
272-73.
[82]
Coleman v MacLennan 78 Kan 711 at 724; 98 P 281 at 286
(1908).
[83]
Vincent Blasi, “Learned Hand and the Self Government Theory of the
First Amendment” (1990) 61 U Colo L Rev
1.
[84]
Ibid at 15. Professor Blasi excepts “any increased likelihood that
incumbents will be rejected at the polls.” Under
a self-government theory,
this cannot be counted as a harm against which freedom of speech is weighed
since it is exactly this, the
choice of who governs, that free speech is
designed to
foster.
[85]
Abrams v United States, [1919] USSC 206; 250 US 616, 630 (1919) (Holmes J dissenting).
See generally, Greenawalt, above n 75 at 130-41; Schauer, above
n 75 at 15 -
34.
[86] For
criticisms of this notion see Greenawalt, above n 75 at 131-141; Schauer
above n 75 at
28-33.
[87]
J.S. Mill, On Liberty (Elizabeth Rapaport ed 1978)(1st ed 1859) at 15 -
52.
[88]See
Schauer, above n 75 at
33-34.
[89]
Vincent Blasi, “Reading Abrams through the Lens of Schauer”
(1997) 72 Notre Dame L Rev 1343 at
1349.
[90] [1964] USSC 40; 376
US 254, 270, 279
(1964).
[91]
[1964] USSC 40; 376 US 254, 270
(1964).
[92]
See Owen Fiss, “Free Speech and Social Structure” (1986) 71
Iowa L Rev 1405 at 1410. Fiss attacks the traditional protection of free
speech in the United States, pointing to the capacity of major broadcasters
(like the American CBS network) to determine the content of public debate:
The Tradition assumes that by leaving individuals alone, free from the menacing arm of the policeman, a full and fair consideration of all the issues will emerge. The premise is that autonomy will lead to rich public debate . . . when our perspective shifts, as I insist it must, from the street corner to, say, CBS, this assumption becomes highly problematic . . .autonomy . . . might even become destructive of that goal.
He concludes that regulation can correct this distortion that flows from
social structure. “[I]n the modern world the state
can enrich as much as
it constricts public debate”. Ibid at 1415. See also, Cass R
Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (1993) at 203 -
13.
[93] One
criticism of the New York Times rule is that “it encourages sloppy
journalism because the lower the standard of care that is seen as
‘normal’ for
journalists, the harder it will be for public figure
plaintiffs to prove the greater dereliction of ‘recklessness’
required
under the Sullivan rule.” Michael Chesterman, “The
Money or the Truth” [1995] UNSWLawJl 16; (1995) 18 UNSWLJ 300 at
307-08.
[94]
Anthony Lewis, “New York Times v Sullivan
Reconsidered: Time to Return to ‘The Central Meaning of the First
Amendment’” (1983) 83 Colum L Rev 603; Nadine
Strossen, “A Defence of the Aspirations - But not the Achievements - of
the US Rules Limiting Defamation Actions By
Public Officials or Public
Figures” [1986] MelbULawRw 1; (1986) 15 Melb U L Rev
419.
[95]
Although the Supreme Court has limited the category of public figures to those
who have ‘thrust’ themselves into controversy
or voluntarily
attracted fame (see Gertz v Robert Welch Inc [1974] USSC 144; 418 US 323, 352 (1974);
Time Inc v Firestone [1976] USSC 27; 424 US 448 (1976); Hutchinson v Proxmire [1979] USSC 139; 443
US 111 (1979); Wolston v Reader’s Digest Assn Inc [1979] USSC 141; 443 US 157
(1979)), the category of defendants to whom it applies extends beyond public
officials and those involved in public affairs to
figures who have no relation
to the political affairs, criticism of whom bears little relation to the speech
about public affairs
which New York Times was aimed to
protect. Lewis, above n 94 at 622-24 (arguing that individuals should only come
within the New York Times philosophy “when they meet
two tests: prominence in the community and relevance to public affairs”.)
David A Anderson,
“Is Libel Law Worth Reforming?” in John Soloski
and Randall P Bezanson (eds), Reforming Libel Law (1992) at 8. See
generally, Gerald Gunther, Constitutional Law 1094 (12th ed 1991)
at 1094.
[96]
Lewis, above n 94 at 609 - 11. In Herbert v Lando [1979] USSC 71; 441 US 153 (1979) the
Supreme Court rejected a claim for a First Amendment privilege in relation to
pre-trial discovery proceedings; Anderson,
above n 95 at
18-21.
[97]
Anderson, above n 95 at
18.
[98] Lewis,
above n 94 at
614.
[99]
Theophanous (1994)182 CLR 104 at 134 (“[W]e should indicate our
preliminary view that these extensions, other than the extension to cover
candidates for public office, should not form part of our
law.”).
[100]
(1994)182 CLR 104 at
135.
[101]
Under the Australian rule, the defendant must establish, “that it
was unaware of the falsity, that it did not publish recklessly (i.e., not caring
whether the matter
was true or false), and that the publication was
reasonable”. [1994] HCA 46; (1994) 182 CLR 104 at 137. See above n
28.
[102]
(1994)182 CLR 104 at 140-41. See also, above n 28 and
accompanying
text.
[103]
This is a requirement under s 22 of the Defamation Act 1974 (NSW). Morgan v
John Fairfax & Sons Ltd (No 2) (1991) 23 NSWLR 374. New South Wales Law
Reform Commission, Defamation (Report No 75, 1995) at
32.
[104]
(1994)182 CLR 104 at
137.
[105]
Peterson v Advertiser Newspapers Ltd [1995] SASC 5018; (1995) 64 SASR 152. See below nn
141-44 and accompanying
text.
[106]
Hartley v Nationwide New Pty Ltd (1995) 119 FLR 124 at 129 Allen J held
that it is for the judge to determine whether the constitutional defence arises
on the evidence, but that the
“reasonableness” requirement is one
for the
jury.
[107]
Richard A Posner, “Legal Reasoning From the Top Down and From the Bottom
Up” (1992) 59 U Chic L Rev
433.
[108]
Posner notes that John Hart Ely advanced a similar “top down” theory
about constitutional law in general in Democracy and Distrust: A
Theory of Judicial Review (1980). Ibid at
434.
[109]
Justice Brennan approved the High Court’s statement in Loveday v
Sun Newspapers Ltd [1938] HCA 28; (1938) 59 CLR 503 that “[t]here is .
. . no principle of law which entitles a newspaper to publish a defamatory
statement of fact about an individual
merely because the statement is made in
the course of dealing with a matter of public interest”. See [1994] HCA 45; (1994) 182
CLR 211 at 244. Justice Brennan considered that departure from this position
“would be a charter for scandal mongering.” Ibid
at
245.
[110]
[1994] HCA 45; (1994) 182 CLR 211 at
247-49.
[111]
Ibid at
251.
[112]
Ibid.
[113]
Justice Brennan placed four limits on the operation of the privilege: the
subject matter of the defamatory statement must be a matter
of relevant public
interest; the report must be fair and accurate; the maker of the statement must
have or be reasonably believed
by the publisher to have “particular
knowledge of the defamatory matter contained in the statement” and
“[t]he
party defamed must have an opportunity to make a reasonable
response to the defamatory matter”. Ibid at
251-253.
[114]
The principal basis of Justice McHugh’s decision was that on the facts of
the case, the appropriate defence was fair comment,
not qualified privilege.
Ibid at 260. Nevertheless he went on to consider, and extend, the common law of
qualified
privilege.
[115]
Adam v Ward [1917] AC 309 in which a claim of qualified privilege
was upheld in respect of a letter published widely by an Army Council in defence
of an officer
who had been the subject of false defamatory comment in the House
of Commons; Loveday v Sun Newspapers Ltd [1938] HCA 28; (1938) 59 CLR 503 in which the
High Court upheld a claim of qualified privilege in respect of an newspaper
article containing a reply to an attack
on a municipal council made in the same
article. These cases are discussed by McHugh J. [1994] HCA 45; (1994) 182 CLR 211 at
262.
[116] In
Allbutt v General Council of Medical Education and Registration (1889) 23
QBD 400 a claim of qualified privilege was upheld by the English Court of Appeal
in relation to a report to the public removing the name
of a medical
practitioner from the register of practitioners. Dunford Publicity Studios
Ltd v News Media Ownership Ltd [1971] NZLR 961, upheld a defence of
qualified privilege in respect of defamatory comments made by a Minister of the
Crown who had been misled into
commending a road safety campaign, on discovering
the truth. These are discussed by McHugh J. [1994] HCA 45; (1994) 182 CLR 211 at
263.
[117]
[1994] HCA 45; (1994) 182 CLR 211 at
263-64.
[118]
(1994)182 CLR 211 at
265.
[119]
Posner, above n 107 at 435; see also, Larry Alexander, “Bad
Beginnings”, 145 U Pa L Rev 57 (1996); Frederick Schauer,
Playing by the Rules (1991) at
183-87.
[120]
Melvin Aron Eisenberg, The Nature of the Common Law (1988) at 76 -
83.
[121]
Ibid at 77; Ronald Dworkin, Law’s Empire (1986) at 312 (arguing
that common law judges ought to decide hard cases by determining the basic
principle underlying decided cases
and determining the principled extension of
that those
cases).
[122]
Eisenberg, above note 120 at
83-87.
[123]
Gerhold v Baker [1918] WN 369. See also Toogood v Spyring [1834] EngR 363; (1834)
1 CM & R 181 at 193; [1834] EngR 363; 149 ER 1044 (qualified privilege protects “the
common convenience and welfare of society.”); Huntley v Ward (1859)
6 CB(NS) 517 (“[T]he law declares [a publication] privileged because the
amount of public inconvenience from the restriction of freedom
of speech or
writing would far out-balance that arising from the infliction of a private
injury.”). See generally, Phillip
Lewis, Gatley on
Libel and Slander (1981) at
186.
[124]
Henwood v Harrison (1872) LR 7 CP at 606 at 622. (“The
principle on which these cases are founded is a universal one, that the public
convenience
is to be preferred to private interests, and that communications
which the interests of society require to be unfettered may freely
be made by
persons acting honestly without actual malice notwithstanding that they involve
relevant comments condemnatory of individuals.”)
See also,
Justin v Associated Newspapers [1967] 1 NSWLR 63 at 75.
See generally, Gatley On Libel and Slander, above n 123
at 187 -
88.
[125]
Baird v Wallace-James (1916) 85 LJPC 193 at 198, cited with approval by
Dixon J, in Guise v Kouvelis [1947] HCA 13; (1947) 74 CLR 102 at 117. See also,
Gatley on Libel and Slander, above n 123 at 192 (“Whether there is a
duty to communicate which the law will recognise as creating a privileged
occasion
depends on all the circumstances and no previous decisions can be
conclusive.”)
[126][1994] HCA 45; (1994)
182 CLR 211 at
240.
[127]
Guise v Kouvelis, [1947] HCA 13; (1947) 74 CLR 102 at
116.
[128]
[1994] HCA 45; (1994) 182 CLR 211 at 249. After reviewing the cases Justice Brennan concludes
“[t]he availability of privilege depends on the evaluation of
factors that
fall roughly, but not exclusively, into two groups: those affecting the public
interest in the function of the body
(its status, constitution and functions and
the circumstances in which the defamatory statement was made) and those
affecting the
public interest in the subject matter of the report (the source of
the defamatory statement, the opportunity for response and any
making of a
finding after an inquiry).” See also, above n
109.
[129]
Stephens [1994] HCA 45; (1994) 182 CLR 211 at
264-65.
[130]
Ibid.
[131]
Cass R Sunstein, Legal Reasoning and Political Conflict (1996) at
35-38.
[132]
See generally, Gatley on Libel and Slander,
above n 123 at
186.
[133]
(1994)182 CLR 211 at
265.
[134]
See text accompanying n 118,
above.
[135]
[1994] HCA 45; (1994) 182 CLR 211 at
267.
[136]
Ibid at
267.
[137]
Ibid
[138]
[1994] HCA 45; (1994) 182 CLR 211 at 267 (“[A]lthough some champions of freedom of
expression might argue otherwise, I am not convinced that society benefits
by
allowing persons to make defamatory comments that injure the reputations of
others unless that comment is fair and based on facts
that are true or ...
attract the defence of qualified
privilege.”)
[139]
For a helpful analysis of various views of common law decision making, see
Eisenberg, above n 120 at
2.
[140]
[1995] SASC 5018; (1995) 64 SASR
152.
[141]
Ibid at 180-81 per Olsson J, at 195-96 per Mullighan
J.
[142] Ibid
at 180.
[143]
Ibid at
196.
[144]
Ibid at 187, 198. Section 22(1) provides for a defence of qualified privilege
where in respect of a publication:
“(a) the recipient has an interest or apparent interest in having information on some subject;
(b) the matter is published to the recipient in the course of giving to him
information on that subject; and
(c) the conduct of the publisher in
publishing that matter is reasonable in the
circumstances”.
[145]
They relied upon Austin v Mirror Newspapers Limited (1985) 3 NSWLR 354;
Morosi v Mirror Newspapers, [1977] 2 NSWLR 749; Wright v Australian
Broadcasting Commission [1977] 1 NSWLR
697.
[146]
(1985) 3 NSWLR 354 at
360.
[147]
Peterson [1995] SASC 5018; (1995) 64 SASR 152 at 187,
198.
[148]
[1994] HCA 46; (1994) 182 CLR 104 at
122.
[149]
Posner, above n 107 at
433.
[150]
David Strauss, “Common Law Constitutional Interpretation” (1996) 63
U Chic L Rev
877.
[151]
See above nn 1,
28.
[152] But
see, below 179 and accompanying
text.
[153]
Harry Kalven Jr., “The New York Times Case: A Note on ‘The
Central Meaning of the First Amendment’” 1964 Sup Ct Rev
191.
[154]
Ibid at
204.
[155]
Ibid.
[156]
As Kalven explains, New York Times v Sullivan represents a judgment by
the Supreme Court that the Alabama rule on fair comment “is closely akin
to making seditious libel
an offense. The Alabama rule therefore violated the
central meaning of the Amendment.” Ibid at
209.
[157]
Ibid
[158] In
his view, the repudiation of seditious libel is one such standard because
“the presence or absence in the law of the concept
of seditious libel
defines the society. . . [if] it makes seditious libel an offense, it is not a
free society no matter what its
other characteristics.” Ibid at
205.
[159]
Gerald Gunther made a similar argument in a different context. In criticising
“case-by-case” or “ad hoc”
balancing in First Amendment
decision making, he argued:
A Supreme Court opinion should strive for more than a ‘fair balancing’ in the individual case before the Court. It should also provide the maximum possible guidance for lower courts and litigants. An excessively particularized opinion lacks that quality. There must at least be an articulation of the criteria that guide the resolution of the value conflicts in a particular case . . . Moreover, especially when sensitive First Amendment values are involved, the risks of case-by-case adjudication may be too great and broader prophylactic rules may be appropriate.
Gerald Gunther, “The Case of Justice Powell” (1972) 24 Stan L
Rev 1001 at
1026-7.
.
[160]
Vincent Blasi, “The Pathological Perspective and the First
Amendment” (1985) 85 Colum L Rev 449. See also, Gunther above n
159.
[161]
Kalven, above n 153 at 209 -
210.
[162]
Stephens [1994] HCA 45; (1994) 182 CLR 211 at
264.
[163]
See, text accompanying above nn
123-31.
[164]
Blasi, above n
160.
[165]
Gerald Gunther makes this point in his critique of Alexander Bickel.
See Bickel above n 52; Gerald Gunther,
“The Subtle Vices of the ‘Passive Virtues’” (1964)
64 Colum L Rev 1. To make his point, Gunther takes Bickel’s
suggestion that there exists a discretion to refuse to hear a case for
“lack
of ripeness”. That is, the case is not before the Court in
the most advantageous posture for decision. Gunther says “the
lack of
‘ripeness’ he mentions does not seem to be of constitutional
dimensions. He does not have the article III requirement
of concreteness in
mind; this appears to be a use of ‘ripeness’ as ‘merely a
conclusionary label,’ as merely
a formula to obscure the ground of
‘jurisdictional’ dismissal.” Ibid at
15.
[166]
Ashwander v TVA [1960] USSC 29; 297 US 288 (1936), see above n 50 and
accompanying
text.
[167]
Frederick Schauer, “Ashwander Revisited” 1995 Sup Ct Rev
71.
[168]
Gunther, above n 165 at
21.
[169]
Schauer, above n 167 at
81-86.
[170]
Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire, at 225
(1986).
[171]
McGinty v Western Australia (1996)186 CLR 140 at 235-36 per McHugh J.
(“I regard the reasoning in Nationwide News, Australian Capital
Television, Theophanous and Stephens in so far as it invokes an
implied principle of representative democracy as fundamentally wrong and as an
alteration of the Constitution without the authority of the people under s 128
of the Constitution.”); at 291 per Gummow J (“[T]he process of
constitutional interpretation by which this principle was derived . . . and
the
nature of the implication . . . departed from previously accepted methods of
constitutional interpretation. If it now were sought
to apply the principle
then the need for further examination of it would arise.”) See also, the
comments of Dawson J during
the hearings in Levy v Victoria. Transcript,
6 August 1996, p
40.
[172]
[1997] HCA 25; (1997) 145 ALR 96 at
99.
[173]
Ibid at
100.
[174]
[1996] HCA 48; (1996) 186 CLR 140 at
169.
[175]
This was the basis of Justice McHugh’s dissent in Theophanous. He
held that there is “no support in the Constitution for an implication that
the institution of representative government or representative democracy is part
of the Constitution independently of ss 1, 7, 24, 30 and 41” and
consequently that there is “nothing - in the text of the Constitution, in
the Convention Debates or in principles of constitutional interpretation
hitherto accepted - that suggests that State legislation
or common law
principles are liable to be overturned by a principle of representative
government or representative democracy that
is implied in the
Constitution.” [1994] HCA 46; (1994) 182 CLR 104 at 199, 205. See also, McGinty
[1996] HCA 48; (1996) 186 CLR 140 at 232 - 35 per McHugh J, at 291 per Gummow
J.
[176]
[1996] HCA 48; (1994) 186 CLR 140 at
234.
[177]
[1997] HCA 25; (1997) 145 ALR 96 at
112.
[178]
These require that the members of the Senate and the House of Representatives be
“directly chosen by the people” of each
State and of the
Commonwealth,
respectively.
[179]
[1997] HCA 25; (1997) 145 ALR 96 at 104. According to the High Court, the relevant context is
provided by s 1 (vesting the power of the Commonwealth in the Parliament); s 8
and s 30 (electors for the Senate and the House of Representatives to vote only
once); s 25 persons of any race disqualified from voting at elections not be
counted in determining electorates under s 24); s 13 (six years to be the
longest term served by a Senator) and s 28 (the House of Representatives to
continue for no longer than three
years).
[180]
Ibid at 825. The High Court relied on s 6 (requiring a session of Parliament
at least once a year); s 83 (requiring that money to be appropriated from the
treasury by law); s 62 (executive power of the Queen exercised on the initiative
and advice of ministers); s 64 (Ministers required to sit in Parliament); s 49
(adopting the “powers privileges and immunities” of the House of the
Parliament of the United
Kingdom).
[181]
Ibid at
106
[182]
Ibid at
107.
[183]
Ibid.
[184]
Ibid.
[185]
Above nn 31-34 and accompanying text.
[186][1994] HCA 46; (1994) 182 CLR 104 at 126.
[187]Ibid at 164
- 165. He notes also that to exclude the common law and from constitutional
scrutiny would allow courts to undermine
the freedom of political communication
through development of the common law. For example, it is conceivable that the
common law
could make actionable a statement which relates to the core of the
constitutional freedom, such as a comment about the suitability
for office of
the Prime Minister. Kent Greenawalt, Fighting Words (1995) at 15. As
Professor Greenawalt notes, however, this problem is mitigated if the common law
is developed in accordance with
constitutional values.
Ibid.
[188][1997] HCA 25; (1997)
145 ALR 96 at 107.
[189]Ibid at 109.
[190]Ibid at
109-10.
[191]
See above nn 65-67 and accompanying
text.
[192]
[1997] HCA 25; (1997) 145 ALR 96 at
112.
[193]
The High Court also held that, even without the common law extension of
qualified privilege, s 22 of the Defamation Act of NSW “ensures that the
New South Wales law of defamation does not place an undue burden on
communications falling within
the protection of the Constitution.” Ibid at
118.
[194]
[1997] HCA 25; (1997) 145 ALR 96 at
115.
[195]
Ibid at
116.
[196]
Ibid at
115.
[197]
[1997] HCA 25; (1997) 145 ALR 96 at
116.
[198]
[1997] HCA 25; (1997) 145 ALR 96 at
115.
[199]
Ibid at
112.
[200]
McGinty [1996] HCA 48; (1996) 186 CLR 140 at 231-32 per McHugh J. (“Underlying or
overarching doctrines may explain or illuminate the meaning of the text or
structure
of the Constitution but such doctrines are not independent sources of
the powers, authorities, immunities and obligations conferred by the
Constitution. Top-down reasoning is not a legitimate method of interpreting the
Constitution . . . it is not legitimate to construe the Constitution by
reference to political principles or theories that are not anchored in the text
of the Constitution or necessary implications from its
structure.”)(footnote
omitted).
[201]
Justice McHugh acknowledges in McGinty, that “[a]ny theory of
constitutional interpretation must be a matter of conviction based on some
theory external to the Constitution.” He goes on to justify his theory:
“But since the people have agreed to be governed by a constitution enacted
by a British
statute, it is surely right to conclude that its meaning must be
determined by the ordinary techniques of statutory interpretation
and by no
other means. It must therefore be interpreted . . . according to the ordinary
and natural meaning of its text, read in
the light of its history, with such
necessary implications as derive from its structure.” [1996] HCA 48; (1996) 186 CLR 140
at 230 (footnote
omitted).
[202]
See, above text accompanying nn
153-160.
[203]
Geoffrey Kennett, “Individual Rights, the High Court and the
Constitution” [1994] MelbULawRw 4; (1994) 19 Melb U L Rev 581 at
589-96.
[204]
Dietrich [1992] HCA 57; (1992) 177 CLR 292 at 326 per Deane J, at 362 per Gaudron J.
This has become all the more significant since the High Court’s decision
in Kable v DPP (1996)189 CLR 5 which applies Chapter III limitations to
state courts. For a discussion of a constitutional right to a fair trial,
prior
to Kable, see Janet Hope, “A Constitutional Right to a Fair
Trial? Implications for the Reform of the Australian Criminal Justice
System”
(1996) 24 Fed L Rev 173 at 179-189.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/UMelbLRS/1998/1.html