Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
University of Melbourne Law School Research Series |
Last Updated: 7 June 2012
NAVIGATING THE POLITICS OF CHARITY: REFLECTIONS ON AID/WATCH INC v FEDERAL COMMISSIONER OF TAXATION
JOYCE
CHIA,[*] MATTHEW
HARDING[†]
AND
ANN
O’CONNELL[‡]
This paper was first published in the
University
of Melbourne Law Review, Volume 35, 2011
[This article analyses the decision of the High Court in Aid/Watch Inc v Federal Commissioner of Taxation, in which a majority of the Court ruled that an organisation was not necessarily excluded from charitable status because it had a main or dominant political purpose. The article reflects upon the benefits of the decision, especially its infusion of public law principles into charity law, before discussing the uncertainties generated by the decision. It is argued that, ultimately, the decision exposes a hole in the heart of charity law — the absence of a coherent conception of charity. The article concludes with suggestions as to what a coherent conception of charity might look like, and how it might help solve perennial puzzles in charity law.]
CONTENTS
I INTRODUCTION
On 1 December 2010, a
majority of the High Court held in Aid/Watch Inc v
Federal Commissioner of Taxation
(‘Aid/Watch’)[1]
that an organisation was not necessarily excluded from charitable status (or its
resulting tax concessions) because it had a main
or dominant political purpose.
This decision has two obvious effects: advocacy organisations are now eligible
for charitable status,
including for tax purposes; and charities can engage more
openly and actively in advocacy. The Aid/Watch decision has therefore,
and rightly, been celebrated by the charitable
sector.[2] The decision
should also be celebrated for another reason: its infusion of public law
principles into charity law.
Yet the decision seems to raise more questions
than it answers, and ultimately, it exposes the hole in the heart of charity law
—
the absence of a coherent and contemporary conception of the purpose and
role of charity. This article concludes by examining some
of the puzzles of the
legal concept of charity, and by suggesting how a coherent conception, and the
infusion of public law principles,
might assist in the development of charity
law post-Aid/Watch.
The article begins by explaining the legal
context, focusing on the political purposes doctrine that Aid/Watch
rejected and the debate concerning that doctrine. It then analyses the different
decisions in the Aid/Watch litigation, before providing three different
reflections on Aid/Watch: celebration, deflation, and speculation on the
future evolution of charity law.
II THE LEGAL CONTEXT
A The Significance and Meaning of Charity
Whether
an organisation is a ‘charity’ at law (that is, has charitable
status) is principally important for two
reasons.[3]
First, ‘charitable’ trusts are valid while other trusts for purposes
are generally not,[4]
and there are other privileges that facilitate the validity of charitable
trusts.[5] Second, and
practically more important today, charitable status grants access to a range of
tax concessions, such as exemptions from
income tax; concessions in relation to
goods and services tax (‘GST’); and rebates in respect of fringe
benefits tax
(‘FBT’).[6]
The organisation must, however, be ‘endorsed’ by the Australian
Taxation Office
(‘ATO’).[7]
Income tax deductions for donors and exemptions from FBT are also relevant to
charities, but in general these charities must be ‘public
benevolent
institutions’ or otherwise specified in the
legislation.[8]
‘Charity’
has a technical meaning in the common law, developed over centuries of case law.
Importantly, this common law
meaning has long been held to govern references to
‘charity’ in taxation
legislation,[9]
despite the inherent tension between the policies of trusts law and taxation
law.[10]
The common law meaning of ‘charity’ has long been criticised as
unduly complex and
anachronistic,[11]
and in 2001 the ad hoc Inquiry into the Definition of Charities and Related
Organisations (‘Sheppard Inquiry’) proposed
replacing it with an
expanded statutory
definition.[12]
While this proposal was not ultimately adopted in
Australia,[13] it
proved influential overseas, with the various jurisdictions of the United
Kingdom (‘UK’) as well as Ireland eventually
adopting similar
statutory
definitions.[14] The
Australian government has recently revived the proposal for a statutory
definition of
‘charity’.[15]
In order to qualify as a charity under the common law definition, an
organisation must fall within one of four ‘heads’
of charity,
commonly known as the ‘Pemsel heads’ after the case where the
classification was first
adopted.[16]
These are: the relief of the poor, aged or impotent; the advancement of
education; the advancement of religion; and the fourth ‘head’,
a
residual category, of ‘other purposes beneficial to the community’.
To determine which ‘head’ a charity
might fall into, courts
typically examine the objects and powers of the organisation in its rules or
constitution (and, if necessary,
its
activities)[17] as a
whole in order to ‘characterise’ its purposes.
If an organisation
falls into the first three heads, it is traditionally presumed to be ‘of
public benefit’ (that is,
it is beneficial and it benefits a sufficient
section of the
public).[18]
However, if the organisation potentially falls into the fourth
‘head’, public benefit must be proved and, further, its
purpose must
be either listed or analogous to one of the 10 specific purposes in the preamble
to the Statute of Charitable Uses 1601, 43
Eliz 1, c 4 (‘Statute of Charitable
Uses’).[19]
B The Political Purposes Doctrine
These basic rules are supplemented by rules refining the parameters of charity, such as the rule that a purpose that is illegal or against public policy cannot be charitable.[20] Most relevantly, one of these rules traditionally disqualified from charitable status any organisation with a main or dominant political purpose (the ‘political purposes doctrine’). The doctrine originated in Lord Parker’s statement in Bowman v Secular Society Ltd (‘Bowman’) in 1917:
a trust for the attainment of political objects has always been held invalid, not because it is illegal, for every one is at liberty to advocate or promote by any lawful means a change in the law, but because the Court has no means of judging whether a proposed change in the law will or will not be for the public benefit, and therefore cannot say that a gift to secure the change is a charitable gift.[21]
The
doctrine was fully established in National Anti-Vivisection
Society v Inland Revenue Commissioners
(‘National Anti-Vivisection
Society’),[22]
which held that the purpose of changing the law — in this case, abolishing
the practice of vivisection — was a political
purpose that disqualified
the organisation from charitable status. The scope of the doctrine was expanded
in the later case of McGovern v Attorney-General,
which defined political purposes broadly to include: furthering the interests of
a particular political party; procuring changes
in the laws of a country; and
procuring a reversal of government policy or governmental decisions in a
country.[23] Case law
even supports the extension of the doctrine to the purpose of supporting the
maintenance of the present
law,[24] although this
aspect of the doctrine is more
controversial.[25]
In
Australia, judges have accepted that the doctrine applies, albeit somewhat
reluctantly.[26] In
1938, the High Court held in Royal North Shore
Hospital of Sydney v Attorney-General
(NSW) (‘Royal North
Shore’)[27]
that it was not a political object to provide a prize for the best essay
promoting the extension of technical education in state
schools. The Court
unanimously held that applying the doctrine to these facts would stretch the
meaning of ‘political’
too
far[28] — it
would lead to the ‘absurd
conclusion’[29]
that ‘political activity’ extended to anything that might be
associated with political
activity[30] or that
might affect or concern the
state.[31]
However, Latham CJ and Dixon J arguably supported a narrow version of the
doctrine, albeit on differing
bases.[32] Latham CJ
suggested it was not ‘difficult to suggest reasons of public policy which
would prevent recognition ... of a trust
for the promotion of a particular
political object as such, or for the maintenance and advocacy ... of the
principles of a political
party’, because such trusts ‘might become
a public
danger’.[33]
This remark suggests Latham CJ supported only a narrow conception of
‘political purpose’, and viewed the doctrine as
an aspect of the
public policy rule.
More widely cited is Dixon J’s approach which
treated the doctrine as part of the ‘public benefit’ test:
A coherent system of law can scarcely admit that objects which are inconsistent with its own provisions are for the public welfare. Thus, when the main purpose of a trust is agitation for legislative or political changes, it is difficult for the law to find the necessary tendency to the public welfare ...[34]
Dixon
J’s remarks also suggest a relatively narrow scope for the doctrine. He
referred expressly to funding a political
party,[35]
‘influencing or taking part in the government of the
country’[36] and
‘establish[ing] a means of affecting or interfering with government
administration’[37]
as disqualifying political activity, and distinguished these activities from
merely ‘seeking to mould opinion ... [by] propagat[ing]
general views for
the purpose of producing a widespread opinion coinciding with [one’s]
own.’[38]
Recent
Australian cases similarly evidence a critical approach to the doctrine. In
three recent cases, the judges avoided applying
the doctrine to the facts:
Public Trustee v Attorney-General (NSW)
(‘Public
Trustee’),[39]
concerning a body promoting the interests of Aborigines and Torres Strait
Islanders; Attorney-General (NSW) v The NSW
Henry George Foundation Ltd (‘Henry
George’),[40]
concerning a trust promoting the views of a 19th
century economist; and Victorian Women Lawyers’
Association Inc v Federal Commissioner
of Taxation (‘Victorian Women
Lawyers’
Association’),[41]
concerning a professional women lawyers’ association.
In all of these
cases, the judges expressed sympathy with criticisms of the doctrine, with
Santow J in particular seeking to narrow
its scope. For example, his Honour
suggested that charitable status could extend to organisations with the object
of introducing
new law ‘consistent with the way the law is
tending’,[42]
and rejected its application to trusts whose main object was to maintain the
status
quo.[43]
Although Young CJ in Eq declined to follow Santow J’s approach in the
Henry George case, his Honour criticised the supposed rationale
for the doctrine and the case law distinguishing between trusts for
‘educational’
purposes and trusts promoting
‘propaganda’.[44]
Similarly, French J observed in Victorian Women
Lawyers’ Association that the doctrine was ‘not well
defined and is more difficult of application today having regard to the change
in social conditions
since [Bowman] and the involvement of legislatures
in areas unthought of at that
time’[45]
— as indeed Latham CJ had recognised even in
1938.[46]
C The Treatment of Advocacy Overseas
The reception of the
political purposes doctrine has been mixed even within those countries sharing
the English tradition of ‘charity
law’. In England itself (and
Wales), the effect of the doctrine has been partly mitigated by the inclusion of
inherently ‘political’
purposes (such as the promotion of human
rights) in the statutory list of charitable
purposes,[47] and by
less restrictive guidance by the Charity Commission of England and
Wales.[48]
Similarly, Ireland’s charity legislation includes in its definition of
charitable purposes inherently ‘political’
purposes.[49] The Act
also expressly disqualifies political parties, bodies promoting political
parties or candidates, and bodies promoting a political
cause ‘unless the
promotion of that cause relates directly to the advancement of the charitable
purposes of the
body’.[50]
In
Canada, the courts have tended to apply the doctrine
strictly,[51] and the
doctrine has also been entrenched in its taxation legislation through a
definition that was intended to clarify that ancillary
and incidental political
activity was
acceptable.[52]
However, the Charities Directorate has issued
guidance[53] which
appears to take a more liberal approach. For example, ‘political
activity’ is confined to explicit communications
either relating to
contacts with or pressure on officials, or explicit communications to the public
of an organisation’s stance
on an
issue.[54] The
guidance also excludes from the definition of ‘political activity’
public awareness campaigns about the charity’s
work or related issues and
direct representations to political representatives or public officials, as long
as they are non-partisan,
connected and subordinate to the charitable purposes
of the
organisation.[55]
Finally, the Charities Directorate’s guidance is that a charity can safely
spend 10 per cent of its income on political activity,
with slightly higher
limits for smaller
charities.[56]
The
United States (‘US’) has been the most liberal in its common law
treatment of advocacy, as its courts have ultimately
not adopted the
doctrine.[57] Instead,
advocacy is permissible as long as the ‘means proposed are peaceful, in
accordance with law and public
policy’.[58]
Indeed, the US courts have tended to take a much more positive view of advocacy,
most famously expressed in Taylor v Hoag:
To hold that an endeavour to procure, by proper means a change in a law is in effect to attempt to violate that law would discourage improvement in legislation and tend to compel us to continue indefinitely to live under laws designed for an entirely different state of society. Such view is opposed to every principle of our government, based on the theory that it is a government ‘of the people, by the people and for the people[’] ...[59]
However,
US taxation legislation is not as liberal, with § 501(c)(3) of the
Internal Revenue Code entrenching two prominent
restrictions.[60] The
first restriction disqualifies organisations from tax exempt status under that
provision if a ‘substantial part’
of their activities involves
propaganda or influencing legislation (the ‘lobbying’
restriction).[61]
However, organisations can elect to be assessed against an alternative
‘quantitative’ test that sets out a permissible
level of expenditure
on lobbying activities depending on the income of the organisation (the
‘safe harbour’
provisions).[62] The
‘electioneering’ restriction prohibits participating or intervening
in political
campaigns.[63]
Finally, under § 4945 of the Internal Revenue Code
private foundations are penalised through excise taxes if they engage in any
‘lobbying’ activities.
Outside of the common law world,
non-governmental organisations are not generally subject to any sector-specific
restrictions. This
is true even of one of the constituent parts of the United
Kingdom, Scotland. Scotland, with its distinctive legal system that mixes
civil
and common law features, has its own tradition of charity law which takes a more
liberal approach to political activities.
As the Scottish regulator advises:
The Scottish charity test ... does not prevent charities from campaigning or lobbying to change the law or the policy of public bodies where this is in furtherance of their charitable purposes. Nor would it prevent such campaigning being a charity’s main activity.[64]
Perhaps the starkest contrast is with the Council of Europe, which has specifically recommended that non-governmental organisations[65] should enjoy ‘the right to freedom of expression’, and in particular:
The recommendation of the Council of Europe also includes guidance that
NGOs should be assisted in the pursuit of their objectives through public funding and other forms of support, such as exemption from income and other taxes or duties on membership fees, funds and goods received from donors or governmental and international agencies, income from investments, rent, royalties, economic activities and property transactions, as well as incentives for donations through income tax deductions or credits.[68]
Therefore, the European position is that tax benefits should exist alongside charitable advocacy and even promotion of a political candidate or party.
III THE CASE AGAINST THE POLITICAL PURPOSES DOCTRINE
The political purposes doctrine has long been criticised, both in Australia and overseas.[69] Drawing from this literature, the ‘case against’ the doctrine can be summarised in terms of a pyramid of arguments, consisting of four primary levels, with the most narrowly based legalistic arguments perhaps most prominent at the top, but ultimately supported by broader normative arguments.
A A Specious Doctrine
At the top level is the
argument that the doctrine rests on shaky legal ground (the
‘speciousness’ argument). Most frequently,
it is noted that Lord
Parker misread the
authorities,[70] and
that the doctrine emerges only in the 20th century,
contradicting earlier cases that clearly accepted ‘political’
organisations as
charities.[71]
At a
slightly broader level, critics contest the supposed rationales for the
doctrine.[72]
Three rationales can be discerned from the authorities:
The
Bowman rationale can be interpreted literally as suggesting that judges
are incapable of determining public benefit, or alternatively as
reflecting the
constitutional claim that judges should not decide political
questions.[77]
The literal interpretation is easily dismissed because judges are required to
determine public benefit all the time in charity
law.[78]
More generally, judges often call for changes to the law, and there are
‘few people better qualified’ to assess the value
of such
changes.[79]
The
second argument can also be similarly dismissed as, at best, hopelessly
old-fashioned. It rests on a mythical view of the ‘eternal
correctness’ of the law that has long been exploded; wrongly assumes that
legislation or case law has decisively settled the
‘issue’ in favour
of one side or another; and is hard to reconcile with practices of governance
that assume an ongoing
need for law
reform.[80]
Finally, the ‘constitutional’ rationale reflects a very
circumscribed and anachronistic view of the constitutional role
of judges which,
in any event, does not apply in Australia. This highly deferential view
permeated English public law in the first
half of the
20th century, and was clearly reflected in the limited
scope of judicial
review.[81] It chimes
still with judges committed to the law as a ‘neutral’ discipline
removed from the ‘political’ fray,
as reflected by the reaction of
some judges to proposals for bills of rights in
Australia.[82] Yet the
contemporary judicial landscape is one in which judges are frequently required
to resolve politicised issues, and the Australian Constitution
itself makes the High Court the ultimate arbiter on matters such as the federal
division of power, the constitutionality of legislation,
and the legality of
government action — all matters of the highest political importance.
B Competing Rights and Values
At the next level of the
pyramid are arguments about the conflict between the doctrine and competing
legal rights and values. While
the most obvious competing legal right is that of
freedom of expression, other rights and values include freedom of association,
freedom of
religion,[83]
equality of
treatment,[84]
the right and value of political
participation,[85] and
the need for certainty in the
law.[86]
In
jurisdictions where these rights are expressly guaranteed, the argument is often
whether restrictions on advocacy violate such
guarantees.[87]
The US and Canadian courts have, however, rejected these arguments in relation
to freedom of expression, on the basis that such restrictions
do not restrain
speech but rather withhold tax subsidies from such
speech.[88]
A
broader, and better, argument is that the doctrine sits uneasily, at best, with
these legal and political principles and values.
It is this argument that
succeeded before the High Court in Aid/Watch, as is discussed later.
However, outside the US, the focus of the literature has been the conflict
between the doctrine and the need
for certainty, a principle that is so deeply
embedded in our understanding of law that it has taken on a non-political
flavour.
This argument is both simple and virtually incontestable. A
qualitative test allowing ‘ancillary’ or ‘incidental’
political activity creates an intolerable degree of uncertainty when the
consequences imperil the very existence and financial viability
of the
organisation. This uncertainty is also compounded by ignorance of the
permissible scope of political
activity.[89]
The result is a ‘chilling effect’ which deters organisations from
engaging in any political activity or from applying
for charitable
status,[90]
and which also distorts the preferences of donors and the structures of
organisations.[91]
The mainstream approach is to argue for a more generous, clear and
principled distinction between charity and
politics.[92] For
example, advocacy could be distinguished from politics as the former seeks to
achieve public interest rather than private
advantage,[93] or
because advocacy determines a ‘basic human good’ while politics is a
process.[94]
Alternatively, distinctions could be made relating to the degree of consensus
about the good of the political
object[95]
or the partisan features of the
activity.[96] An
alternative is to provide for ‘quantitative’ safe harbour tests, as
used in the US and
Canada,[97]
or to create new forms of advocacy organisations eligible for fewer tax
concessions and subject to more stringent reporting
requirements.[98]
C The Political Process
The third level of the
argument is that political speech by charities enriches the political process by
encouraging political
debate,[99]
facilitating citizen participation and engagement, and promoting political
pluralism.[100]
Public benefit in this view resides in the generation of public debate itself,
rather than in the particular
cause,[101]
so both sides of a public debate could be deemed
charitable.[102]
This argument directly addresses two rationales expressed in the US
literature for the restrictions on advocacy: a fear that political
speech by
charities will only encourage political paralysis and polarisation and promote
propaganda;[103]
and the argument that the tax subsidies enjoyed by charities would unfairly skew
the balance of political
speech.[104]
The first rationale is grounded in a restrictive view of the appropriate sphere
of political debate. The second rationale fails to
recognise that the
distribution of political speech is already unequal and will always be
‘imperfect’,[105]
and that if anything charitable advocacy will mitigate those inequalities, by
representing under-represented
interests[106] and
improving the quality of decision-making through charities’ expertise and
connection with the
voiceless.[107]
These benefits are enhanced by the independence of charities from the
government.
D The Function of Charity
At the base of the
pyramid of arguments against the political purposes doctrine is the argument
that the distinction between ‘charity’
and ‘politics’
misconceives the true role of charity. Instead, advocacy and engagement with
politics are better conceptualised
as an essential, and perhaps the most
effective,[108]
method of achieving charitable
purposes.[109] The
distinction is also anachronistic, because the expansion of government and
legislative activity has enlarged the sphere of ‘politics’
dramatically,[110]
and because of trends such as devolution in service delivery, decreasing policy
development by governments, and increasing
consultation.[111]
This argument addresses the justifications occasionally offered in support
of the political purposes doctrine that rely upon an intuitive
distinction
between charity and politics. These justifications include that the ‘true
nature’ of charity is not
political,[112] that
advocacy will divert resources away from
charity,[113]
that donors need to be protected from the ‘misuse’ of their
donations, and that too close an association with politics
would undermine the
‘brand’ of
charity.[114]
These suggested justifications, however, do not withstand scrutiny.
First,
the idea that charity is not political presupposes a restrictive concept of
charity that would exclude, for example, campaigns
against slavery or most
environmental campaigns, both of which have been recognised as charitable at
law.[115] Second,
the idea of diversion similarly depends upon a pre-existing distinction between
advocacy and charity, and fails to recognise
that sometimes the most effective
way of addressing a social problem is a change in legislation or policy. Third,
the argument that
donors need to be protected from misuse of donations or that
the charity ‘brand’ will be tainted is not sustained by
any evidence
that donors do not want their donations to be spent on advocacy — indeed,
there is some evidence to the
contrary.[116]
Aid/Watch itself found that it received similar amounts for its separate
charitable and advocacy
funds.[117]
The argument is also paternalistic, assuming that the ‘law needs to
protect public charities from
themselves.’[118]
A more radical approach is to argue that the distinction between charity and
politics itself is artificial, as charitable purposes
naturally involve
questions about the distribution of political power and issues of law and
policy.[119]
This reflects a broader conception of ‘politics’. Chesterman, for
example, argues that charity is ‘political’
in the sense that it
empowers people to influence or control the conduct of the beneficiaries, and
that asserting a role for charity
implicitly supports the continuation of an
unequal social
structure.[120]
Drassinower, on the other hand, posits a distinction between changes in a
society and changes of a society, which distinguishes charity and
politics through the level of fundamental political agreement underpinning
them.[121]
IV AID/WATCH IN THE COURTS
A The Factual Context
The
Aid/Watch decision is a landmark in this broader debate about the
relationship between charity and politics. The facts of the case are simple
enough. Aid/Watch is an activist member-based association concerned with
improving Australia’s foreign aid and trade
policies.[122] The
purposes listed in its constitution focus on ensuring that such policies accord
with environmental principles and empower local
communities, especially women
and indigenous
people.[123]
Its activities include monitoring aid and trade policies; producing research
reports on Australia’s policies and practices;
campaigning for changes to
those policies and practices; and participating in conferences, international
networks and public awareness
campaigns.[124]
In some senses, Aid/Watch was a perfect test case. On the one hand,
it concerned what might be thought of as the quintessence of modern charity,
humanitarian
overseas aid. As the poverty of developing nations becomes both
more acute and visible in a globalised world, humanitarian overseas
aid has
become the most visible face of the ‘core’ of charity, the relief of
poverty. The ‘charitable’ nature
of humanitarian overseas aid is
enhanced by its association with the most powerful charity brands, such as World
Vision and the Red
Cross, and by the reliance of the sector on public
donations.[125]
However, foreign aid also reflects the ‘mixed’ nature of the
sector, with the extensive involvement of government and
the increasing
influence of the private sector in this field. Government funding, known as
‘official development assistance’,
will amount to $4.3 billion in
2011–12,[126]
while international aid organisations raise annually around $1
billion.[127]
International development organisations are often financially reliant upon
overseas development aid funding, and their activities
are tightly regulated by
AusAID and the peak body, the Australian Council for International
Development.[128] As
well, there has been a trend towards mixing market principles with traditional
aid practices, marked by the rise of microfinance
and projects driven by
corporate
self-interest.[129]
Foreign aid has also been discursively transformed into ‘international
development’, with its accompanying emphasis on
local capacity-building
and empowerment and the consequences of exploitative corporate
practices.[130] This
is fostered by a broader shift from talking of ‘charity’ to talking
of ‘global justice’, and from focusing
on states to focusing on
human rights — a paradigm shift that Aid/Watch clearly represents. Indeed,
somewhat ironically, Aid/Watch
proclaims as its first value: ‘We believe
in solidarity not
charity’.[131]
B The Facts and Issues
Aid/Watch was endorsed
by the ATO as a ‘charitable institution’ for the purposes of income
tax with effect from 14 July
2000, and for the purposes of FBT and GST effective
from 1 July
2005.[132] However,
on 2 October 2006, the Commissioner of Taxation revoked these
endorsements.[133]
The ATO’s objections were twofold. First, it argued that
Aid/Watch’s purpose was to monitor the aid program, not deliver
aid.
Second, the ATO objected to three ‘political’ activities: urging the
public to write to the government to put pressure
on the Burmese regime;
delivering an ironic birthday cake to the World Bank; and raising concerns about
the developmental impacts
of the Australia–US Free
Trade
Agreement.[134]
Aid/Watch’s objection was disallowed on 6 March 2007, and two days later
Aid/Watch sought review of the decision by the Administrative
Appeals Tribunal
(‘AAT’).[135]
The case raised two principal legal issues: first, whether Aid/Watch’s
activities could properly be characterised as falling
within either the first or
second Pemsel head (poverty or education) rather than the fourth head;
and second, whether Aid/Watch was disqualified by reason of the political
purposes doctrine.
C The AAT Decision
On 28 July 2008, the
President of the AAT, Downes J, found for Aid/Watch on both
issues.[136]
Aid/Watch was found to fall within both the first and second Pemsel heads
and, to the extent it did not fall within either, it fell within the fourth
head.[137] Aid/Watch
was also found to be emphasising particular priorities in an existing government
policy rather than challenging government
policy, and so did not fall afoul of
the political purposes
doctrine.[138]
Downes
J held that Aid/Watch’s purposes included relieving poverty,
notwithstanding that this was not articulated in its constitution,
because the
object of relieving poverty was ‘so fundamental to aid’ that it need
not be expressly
stated.[139]
Promoting the effectiveness of aid advanced the relief of poverty, even though
it did not directly relieve
poverty.[140]
Aid/Watch was found to advance education because of the scholarship of its
publications.[141]
The public benefit of its reports was also compared favourably to the public
benefit of researching Shakespearean manuscripts (which
had previously been
found
charitable).[142]
Finally, it would ‘not be surprising’ if the organisation also
satisfied the fourth Pemsel
category,[143] in
which case foreign aid could be seen as analogous to delivering public
infrastructure, a purpose implied by the preamble of the
Statute
of Charitable
Uses.[144]
Downes
J further characterised Aid/Watch as encouraging the government’s policy
of providing overseas aid and protecting the
environment, although it was
proposing ‘different
priorities’[145]
for that policy as to the ‘nature and extent and means of
delivery’[146]
of aid. This was so even though some of Aid/Watch’s activities
‘might be thought to be at the edges of appropriate conduct’
and
‘somewhat
aggressive’.[147]
However, Downes J did appear to suggest that extreme conduct (not evinced here)
could result in the organisation losing its charitable
quality.[148]
Significantly, Downes J also doubted whether ‘robust attempts to
influence government
policy’[149]
should continue to be excluded from charitable status, in the light of
contemporary governance practices such as the entrenchment
of consultation
practices, freedom of information and other administrative law
reforms.[150] His
Honour also agreed with criticisms of the rationale of the political purposes
doctrine,[151] and
suggested it applied only to charities under the fourth Pemsel
head.[152]
D Aid/Watch in the Full Federal Court
The AAT’s
decision, however, was reversed on appeal to the Full Federal Court on 23
September 2009.[153]
The unanimous Court largely agreed with the AAT on the issue of
characterisation. Like the AAT, the Full Court held that promoting
the
efficiency of aid delivery would (albeit
indirectly)[154] aid
the relief of
poverty,[155] and
extended this to Aid/Watch’s environmental objectives, since unsustainable
aid ‘may destroy ecosystems upon which
communities rely in order to
prosper.’[156]
Although it was not strictly necessary, the Court also found that Aid/Watch was
‘educational’, agreeing with the AAT
that the publication of
substantial research reports satisfied the element of
education,[157] and
rejecting the submission that ‘education’ had to involve structured
training or
teaching.[158]
However, the Full Court held that Aid/Watch was disqualified from charitable
status by the political purposes
doctrine.[159] In
its view, Aid/Watch’s objectives could only be achieved by campaigning to
alter government policy, and its primary goal
was to influence the
government.[160] Its
attempt to persuade the government necessarily involved criticism of, and an
attempt to change, government activity and policy,
and thus Aid/Watch’s
main purpose and activity were
political.[161] The
Court did, however, reject the AAT’s apparent suggestion that ‘undue
emphasis’ on political means could disqualify
an organisation from
charitable
status.[162]
The
Court then considered whether charitable and political purposes were in this
case mutually exclusive, acknowledging Santow J’s
point in Public
Trustee that an object of changing government policy may not be in such
contradiction with government policy as to become ‘automatically
“political”’.[163]
The Court agreed that, on one level, it could be said that Aid/Watch’s
objectives did not conflict with the government’s
objective to deliver aid
efficiently with due regard to environmental concerns. However,
Aid/Watch’s aim was to ensure that
aid should conform to its view of the
best way to achieve this objective, disregarding other factors that a government
would have
to
consider.[164]
The
Court not only accepted that it was bound by the political purposes
doctrine,[165] but
also accepted both the literal and the constitutional rationales for the
doctrine. The Court observed that judges could not judge
public benefit in
‘all circumstances’; that they were not ‘equipped to consider
all the factors that have resulted
in decisions as to what foreign aid is to be
provided and how it is to be delivered’; and that they were ‘not
entitled
to enter into such
debates.’[166]
Ultimately, the Court held that it could not judge public benefit because the
issue was, in the end, one for
government.[167]
E Aid/Watch in the High Court
The High Court heard
argument on 15 and 16 June
2010.[168] At the
hearing, the primary argument of counsel for Aid/Watch was that both the AAT and
the Full Court had found that Aid/Watch fell
within the first two Pemsel
heads, and therefore that it benefited from the presumption of public benefit
which had not been
rebutted.[169]
Counsel’s main contention was that, as Downes J had suggested, the
political purposes doctrine applied only to the fourth head
of
charity.[170] This
was despite Aid/Watch’s written submission which suggested more broadly
that ‘public benefit’ could reside
in the existence of public debate
itself.[171]
Instead, Aid/Watch focused on the ‘speciousness’ of the
doctrine, arguing that the doctrine rested on ‘foundations
of
sand’[172] and
suggesting that the House of Lords in National Anti-Vivisection
Society had relied on the wrong edition of a
textbook.[173]
Counsel only briefly contested the doctrine’s rationales, but after
careful probing, submitted that there was public benefit
from public debate at
least in relation to any of the first three heads of
charity.[174]
Counsel
for the Commissioner of Taxation similarly focused on the issue of
characterisation, submitting that either a dominant political
means or a
dominant political purpose would disqualify an organisation from charitable
status.[175] This
applied to all four Pemsel heads, and it was not possible simply to
combine the desirability of public debate with one of the first three
Pemsel heads. Counsel also argued that the purpose of relieving poverty
was ‘totally missing and, indeed, is antithetical to what
is being
advocated in some areas where there is a conflict between the environment and
poverty and one has to benefit one or benefit
the
other.’[176]
The
interesting point is that both sides chose not to focus on what the judges
clearly saw as the crucial issue — namely, the
political purposes
doctrine. Counsel for Aid/Watch failed to articulate a vision of advocacy as
generally for the public benefit,
or to supply any cogent limits to that broad
principle. Only at the very end of his address did he briefly put forward the
‘functional’
argument that political activity was ‘an inherent
and necessary part’ of the activities of
charities.[177]
In
contrast, the judges sought to focus on broad principle, especially the
normative tension between the doctrine’s proscription
of political speech
by charities and the Constitution’s valorisation of political
communication. This was best put by Hayne J:
a defining characteristic of the society in which this doctrine has defined its application is that of representative and responsible government underpinned by free political exchange and an understanding of what is meant by the term ‘political’ when used, it seems, as a term of disapprobation in contradiction to the approving term ‘charitable’, requires some adjustment.[178]
Counsel
for the Commissioner initially sought to rely on the US and Canadian cases
distinguishing between restraints on free speech
and the withholding of a tax
benefit,[179] and
then on a distinction between ‘promoting public discussion and pushing one
side in a
debate’,[180]
evoking the distinction between education and propaganda in charity
law.[181] Counsel
also contended that there was ‘no particular benefit to poor people or to
the advancement of education in talking about
poverty or
education’[182]
— a view Hayne J swiftly condemned as
anachronistic.[183]
Counsel then resorted to the constitutional rationale of the doctrine, arguing
that ‘it [was] outside the realm of the courts
to make political
judgments’,[184]
although Gummow J was quick to point to the ‘political’ role of the
High Court envisaged by the Constitution, as discussed
above.[185]
The
judges were, however, concerned about the implications of repealing the
doctrine. As French CJ concisely put it:
Ultimately the question ... is if one dispenses with a political purposes exception or disqualification what are the boundaries of community benefit, or public benefit?[186]
The
judges suggested several ‘hard cases’, such as political parties,
societies dedicated to decriminalisation of drug
trafficking, and organisations
dedicated to the repeal of anti-discrimination law. However, counsel for
Aid/Watch refused to be drawn
on this issue, insisting that ultimately the
public benefit of ‘fourth head’ charities had to be decided in each
case
on the
evidence.[187]
The
judges also clearly rejected the suggestion, initially made by
Gummow J,[188]
that the definition of charity in tax legislation should be decoupled from the
common law
definition[189]
— a position later affirmed in the majority
judgment.[190]
F The High Court Decision
On 1 December 2010, a majority of five judges overturned the Full Federal Court’s decision, with Heydon J and Kiefel J writing separate dissents.[191] The key passage in the majority judgment amounted to three short paragraphs. First, the majority characterised Aid/Watch’s activities as falling within the fourth Pemsel head, on the basis that ‘the generation by lawful means of public debate ... concerning the efficiency of foreign aid’ was itself beneficial to the community.[192] Second, it held that public debate concerning government activities within the first three heads (or the balance of the fourth head) fell within the fourth head.[193] The Court, however, expressly left open the question of whether the fourth head
encompasses the encouragement of public debate respecting activities of government which lie beyond the first three heads (or the balance of the fourth head) identified in Pemsel and, if so, the range of those activities.[194]
The majority therefore accepted the line suggested by counsel
for Aid/Watch. Third, the majority ruled that the ‘political
purposes’
doctrine did not apply in Australia, although in a particular
case the ends and means involved could result in a finding that there
was
insufficient public
benefit.[195]
The
rationale of the majority for rejecting the political purposes doctrine was set
out in an earlier passage of its
judgment[196]
discussing Dixon J’s dictum in Royal North Shore
concerning the coherence of the
law.[197] The
majority rejected this argument because the doctrine itself was in tension with
the Constitution. The Constitution was based on representative and
responsible government, included a universal adult franchise, and provided for
constitutional change
through popular referenda, and thus assumed as an
‘indispensable incident’ communication between the executive,
legislature
and electors on matters of government and
politics.[198] The
system itself therefore required ‘agitation’ for legislative and
political change, and assumed that this would contribute
to the public
welfare.[199] This
conclusion was, perhaps, reinforced by the discussion of the shaky legal
foundations of the doctrine, the liberalising effect
of the guidance on
political purposes issued by the Charity Commission of England and Wales, and
the different position taken in
the
US.[200]
The
dissenting judgments took rather different paths. Heydon J’s judgment
might be characterised as a ‘traditionalist’
approach, evincing a
fairly narrow view of ‘public debate’, ‘poverty’ and
‘education’. Heydon
J was clearly influenced by the distinction
between ‘emotional and rhetorical’ propaganda and reasoned
‘debate’
when he contested the characterisation of Aid/Watch as
‘seeking to generate debate’:
The appellant advanced points of view, but it was not generating debate in the sense of stimulating others to contribute competing points of view so that some higher synthesis or more acute understanding of issues might emerge. The appellant was not playing the role of a teacher in charge of a skilfully conducted seminar, or someone deftly presiding over a meeting. The appellant’s activities were designed to ensure that the appellant’s points of view about aid prevailed by ensuring that government did some things and did not do others. ... Those who ran the appellant did not see themselves as philosophers merely talking about the world, or encouraging others to talk about the world: they saw their task as being to change the world. ... The appellant’s views were not put in a manner inviting a response, but in a manner seeking compliance. It did not want dialogue, nor even too long a monologue. The appellant wanted its views to be implemented, not debated. It wanted obedience, not conversation.[201]
The
distinction Heydon J is invoking is a distinction often made in charity law
between ‘reasoned’ discourse and ‘polemical’
discourse.
Yet the effect of this distinction, it appears, is that there is more public
benefit in an organisation that ‘merely
talk[s]’ about the world or
‘presides’ over a seminar than in an organisation that seeks to
‘change the world’.
In this view, there is more value in an
organisation that subscribes to no position than an organisation that stands for
something
and seeks to convince others of it.
Heydon J also found that
Aid/Watch did not relieve poverty as it did not distribute aid and the objective
of relieving poverty was
‘diffused by’ and ‘actually
contradicted by’ other objectives, such as the removal of extractive
industries
which may generate
wealth.[202]
Further, the organisation was not educational, because this was only one of its
objectives and its reports were
‘polemical’.[203]
Having decided Aid/Watch was not charitable, Heydon J decided to leave open the
further issue of the political purposes
doctrine.[204]
While
Heydon J objected to the fact that Aid/Watch did not function as a debating
society, Kiefel J’s primary objection was
that it functioned too much like
one. Her Honour held that there was insufficient public benefit in Aid/Watch
merely asserting its
views.[205] It did
not promote the relief of poverty ‘in any practical
way’,[206] and
it could only do so if its views about the greater effectiveness of aid were in
fact true, which could not be
established.[207]
She also characterised its reports as campaigning rather than
educational.[208]
Finally, the Full Federal Court’s decision that it could not determine
public benefit was ‘plainly
correct’.[209]
Kiefel J’s reasoning is difficult to support, as charity law requires
organisations to prove neither their efficacy nor the
truth of their views. The
reasoning also assumes that expressions of political views do not effect
political or social change, gravely
undervaluing the role of advocacy and public
debate.
Nevertheless, Kiefel J’s dissent came closest to articulating a
more progressive role for charity by referring directly to the
‘functional’ argument about the interrelationship between charity
and politics:
It could scarcely be denied, these days, that it may be necessary for organisations, whose purposes are directed to the relief of poverty or the advancement of education, to agitate for change in the policies of government or in legislation in order to best advance their charitable purposes.[210]
Kiefel J also rejected two of the rationales for the doctrine. Judges could and did judge public benefit, although there may well be ‘practical difficulties’ in doing so.[211] Further, it was not essential to assume the correctness of existing law, because one could consistently maintain the law while recognising the ‘importance and value of public discussion, education and debate about aspects of the law and changes which might be made to it.’[212]
V REFLECTION 1: CELEBRATION
The reaction of
charities to the Aid/Watch decision was generally, and rightly, one of
celebration.[213]
The judgment was a clear and strong rejection of the political purposes
doctrine. It removes a doctrinal anomaly and the muddle it
engendered.
Most
importantly, it paves the way for organisations to primarily and wholly engage
in advocacy, at least within fields of activity
already recognised as
charitable. While this is the clearest legal consequence of the decision, its
practical implications in the
long term are less clear. One intriguing
possibility is that, by encouraging smaller advocacy organisations, it may
restructure parts
of the not-for-profit sector. This is more than a matter of
mere form. An organisation devoted to advocacy may be more effective
in relation
to some issues where, for example, the government is the principal actor or
legislative change is necessary. An advocacy
organisation may also better suit
(as in the case of Aid/Watch) a volunteer member-based organisation. Larger
charitable organisations
may decide to set up separate advocacy organisations in
order to take a more independent approach to advocacy.
The second principal
effect of the decision is to remove the ‘chilling’ uncertainty
caused by the doctrine which had deterred
charities from engaging in
advocacy.[214] This
consequence is less dramatic since organisations could already engage in
ancillary or incidental advocacy, but is likely to
be more practically
significant in the short term than the structural implications.
The most
profound symbolic consequence is that advocacy has been accepted as a legitimate
charitable activity. This will no doubt
shape the charity sector’s
self-conception and its future engagement with government.
A Freedom of Expression
A less obvious cause for
celebration is that the decision directly addresses the normative tension
between the political purposes
doctrine and the principle of freedom of
expression, although this is less prominent in the majority judgment than might
have been
expected after the oral hearing. The irony, of course, is that
Australia’s protection of freedom of expression is limited in
contrast
with that of the US and
Canada,[215]
yet those countries consider similar restrictions on advocacy compatible with
freedom of expression, although principally in relation
to restrictions in tax
legislation.
There are three key limitations to the implied freedom of
political communication in Australia. First, its rationale is that the
Constitution provides for a system of representative
government[216] and
freedom of communication is an ‘indispensable incident’ of that
system.[217] The
doctrine is therefore founded upon a very narrow version of the
‘democratic’ rationale for democracy, namely that
‘[d]emocratic decision making requires discussion and debate as well as
voting, and a significant limit upon its deliberative
process will significantly
limit its democratic
character.’[218]
Second,
that rationale results in the freedom protecting only discussion about
‘political or government matters’ which
is necessary to enable free
and informed electoral
choices,[219]
although this has been relatively generously interpreted, including for example
discussion of the conduct of statutory authorities
and public utilities and, to
some extent, discussion of matters at the local, state or territory
level.[220]
Throughout the world, political or government matters form the very core of the
freedom, and typically warrant greater scrutiny or
justification.[221]
Third, the freedom does not confer personal rights on individuals, but
rather precludes the legislature or executive from curtailing
the
freedom.[222]
However, the freedom will invalidate laws only if: (i) the law effectively
burdens freedom of communication about government or political
matters in its
terms, operation or effect; and (ii) the laws are not reasonably appropriate and
adapted to serve a legitimate end
in a manner which is compatible with the
maintenance of the constitutionally prescribed system of representative and
responsible
government.[223] The
rules of the common law must also be developed by reference to the same
considerations.[224]
What
is most striking is that this peculiarly confined freedom protects exactly the
kind of activity that is proscribed by the political
purposes doctrine. The
political purposes doctrine proscribes exactly the kind of discussion and debate
designed to inform voting
choices — criticism of existing laws and
government policy by those often best placed to observe and understand the
effects
of such laws and policy, especially in relation to typically
under-represented segments of the community. Indeed, the doctrine directly
targets information because it is ‘governmental’ or
‘political’, rather than incidentally restricting political
communication, and is therefore harder to justify as compatible with the implied
freedom.[225] As
Hayne J perceptively observed, the heart of the problem is that the implied
freedom assumes the fundamental ‘public benefit’
of democratic
debate, whereas the political purposes doctrine implicitly views political
speech with
‘disapprobation’.[226]
Further, the implied freedom requires restrictions on political speech to be
‘reasonably appropriate and adapted to serve a
legitimate end’ in a
manner compatible with representative democracy. As discussed above, there is no
principled justification
for targeting the free speech of charities. Nor are the
consequences, both existential and financial, ‘reasonably appropriate
and
adapted’ to any suggested justification. Rather, as argued above, the
restrictions serve to diminish rather than enhance
representative democracy. The
political purposes doctrine is also a common law rule which should be developed
in light of the
freedom,[227] much
as the High Court has diverged from English defamation law to protect this
implied
freedom.[228]
The political purposes doctrine, in effect, upends the hierarchy of values
implicit in Australian public law and in the international
jurisprudence on
freedom of expression. As the majority rightly perceived, the argument that the
political purposes doctrine maintains
the ‘coherence’ of the law
simply fails to recognise the deeper normative incoherence between a
constitutional arrangement
that depends upon freedom of political communication
and a common law doctrine that targets precisely that form of
communication.
This can be seen very clearly in the case of Aid/Watch,
because the organisation acted as a ‘watchdog’ to influence the
‘free and informed’ choice of electors. Indeed, the European Court
of Human Rights has recently equated the role of watchdogs
with that of the
privileged position of the press:
The Court has repeatedly recognised civil society’s important contribution to the discussion of public affairs ... The applicant is an association involved in human rights litigation with various objectives, including the protection of freedom of information. It may therefore be characterised, like the press, as a social ‘watchdog’. In these circumstances, the Court is satisfied that its activities warrant similar Convention protection to that afforded to the press.[229]
Superficially, the Aid/Watch case rests on
Australia’s particular constitutional framework. This helps legitimise
Australia’s departure from common
law doctrine, but may limit the
decision’s utility in other
jurisdictions.[230]
Yet the framework of representative democracy is applicable to most other
comparable jurisdictions and, since most comparable jurisdictions
expressly
guarantee a broader notion of freedom of expression, the reasoning in
Aid/Watch ought to be even more persuasive in those jurisdictions. This
was recognised by Heath J in the recent New Zealand decision Re
Greenpeace of New Zealand Inc, who had
‘no real concerns that the political system in Australia ought to bring
about a different conclusion’, referring
inter alia to the existence of
the guarantees of freedom of thought, conscience and religion, and freedom of
expression in the New Zealand Bill of Rights
Act 1990
(NZ).[231] However,
Heath J held ‘with a degree of reluctance’ that the Court was bound
by an earlier New Zealand Court of Appeal
decision affirming
Bowman.[232]
Greenpeace has indicated it will appeal this decision to the Court of
Appeal.[233]
There is, however, one obvious parallel between the constitutional doctrine
and the political purposes doctrine — the idea of
the appropriate
‘means’ of political communication. In Coleman v
Power, a majority held that insults could constitute ‘political
communication’. Gummow and Hayne JJ noted, for example, that
insults and
‘invective have been employed in political communication at least since
the time of
Demosthenes.’[234]
Callinan J, however, thought that insults were not ‘capable of throwing
light on government or political
matters’,[235]
and were thus
unprotected.[236]
While Heydon J seemed to accept that some political communication was insulting,
he considered that ‘[t]o address insulting
words to persons in a public
place is conduct sufficiently alien to the virtues of free and informed debate
on which the constitutional
freedom rests that it falls outside of
it.’[237] As
Arcioni has argued, Callinan J and Heydon J’s approach ‘painted a
picture of the system of government as they believe
it should exist, or as they
believe it would most effectively operate’, rather than measuring the
freedom against political
reality.[238]
In Aid/Watch, Heydon J similarly disparaged Aid/Watch’s methods
of political communication as failing to generate ‘debate ... so that
some
higher synthesis or more acute understanding of issues might
emerge.’[239]
This echoes Callinan J’s criticisms in Coleman v
Power that the insult in that case generated ‘heat’ rather
than
‘light’[240]
— once again idealising public debate as a sphere of
reason.[241]
Nevertheless, the majority in
Aid/Watch[242]
clearly rejected Heydon J’s narrow construction of public debate as
‘civilised political
discourse’[243]
— a welcome conclusion that recognises the practice and variety of
political speech, especially in the contemporary media landscape.
B Public Law
Another cause of
celebration is that the Aid/Watch decision infuses principles of public
law into charity law. To some extent, this may have been the product of the
happy circumstance
that the solicitors for Aid/Watch were not traditional
charity lawyers, but rather public
lawyers.[244]
This
infusion of public law principles in charity law is welcome, as charity law
involves both private and public aspects. Charity
is inspired by private persons
and takes the form of private organisation, but its motive is to benefit the
public, it acts in the
public sphere, it affects the public, and more often than
not it is supported by the public by way of donations of time and money,
and to
a lesser extent by tax concessions. Yet, because of its historical development
through the private law field of trusts law,
the ‘public’
implications of charity law have too often been obscured or
under-theorised.
While all laws tend to be captive to the historical norms
that shape their evolution, in the case of charity law this is exacerbated
by
two other factors. First, the role of charity has undergone significant
historical shifts. For example, while religion was synonymous
with charity in
medieval times, post-Reformation charity was both secularised and turned into a
primitive form of welfare provision.
In Australia, unlike in the UK, early
charitable institutions were often funded by the state. In the
20th century, the massive growth of the government and
the welfare state radically reshaped the role of charity. The role of charity
has
also been reconfigured by the emergence of fields such as social justice and
environmental
protection.[245]
Centuries of case law have therefore embedded quite different contextual
understandings of charity into legal doctrine.
Second, charity law developed
in the courts of equity, which in the 19th century
became famously inaccessible. The establishment in England and Wales of a
Charity Commission partly offset the decline in
litigation, but has also
inhibited the development of case law. The cost and uncertainty of litigation
continues to deter charities
from litigating and clarifying the
law.[246]
The
private law context of charity law and the mismatch between a slowly developing
law and a rapidly changing social role and context
have combined to produce a
law of charity that fails to give due recognition to the ‘public’
aspects of charity law.
Indeed, although the key to the definition of charity is
‘public’ benefit and the key to the political purpose doctrine
is
the term ‘political’, there is a striking dearth of discussion as to
the meaning of either of these terms, or even
recognition of their multi-layered
nature. Worse, decisions and discussion often proceed on unarticulated and
sometimes unfounded
assumptions concerning the nature and role of charity. By
infusing public law principles into its decision in Aid/Watch, the High
Court points to a way of solving many of the doctrinal puzzles in charity law
— by drawing in more clearly articulated,
and more contemporary, theories
of the public and political arena and the role of charity in them. Some of the
possible implications
of this approach are sketched in the conclusion of this
article.
VI REFLECTION 2: DEFLATION
There were many reasons,
then, to welcome the Aid/Watch decision. Yet, the further one reflects
upon the decision, the more unanswered questions one confronts. For one thing,
the decision
creates uncertainty. On the issue of characterisation, the three
judicial decisions differed considerably. The AAT found that Aid/Watch
relieved
poverty and advanced education, and otherwise fell into the fourth head; the
Full Federal Court agreed but characterised
its primary purpose as
political.
In contrast, the majority of the High Court characterised
Aid/Watch as falling within the fourth Pemsel head, as generating public
debate ‘concerning the efficiency of foreign aid directed to the relief of
poverty’.[247]
The majority did not, however, explain why it had rejected the earlier judicial
characterisations of Aid/Watch’s purposes,
and failed to discuss the
characterisation issue in any detail. Heydon J, on the other hand, strongly
rejected the argument that
Aid/Watch either relieved poverty or advanced
education, based on a narrow construction of ‘poverty’ as a lack of
material
prosperity (so that environmental objectives were possibly opposed to
the relief of poverty) and on a narrow construction of
education.[248]
Kiefel J similarly rejected the characterisation of Aid/Watch as educational and
considered its connection to the relief of poverty
too
remote.[249]
The
decision also fails to provide guidance in key respects. One concern is whether
the decision applies to ‘political activities’
other than generating
public debate, such as private lobbying of government officials or political
campaigning — especially
when read in light of the majority’s
comment that the ‘particular ends and means’ used may disqualify an
organisation
from charitable
status.[250] It is
unclear, therefore, whether Aid/Watch changes the legal position in
relation to organisations such as GetUp! or political parties.
Another
question, left expressly open, is the charitable status of entities engaging in
public debate involving governmental activities
in a field that has not already
been identified as charitable (that is, within the first three Pemsel
heads or the ‘balance of the fourth head’). For example, would an
association formed to oppose government policy on Australian–Chinese
relations be charitable? It is probable that the High Court’s intention
was merely to restrict its ruling to the facts of the
case (by following the
conservative lead of counsel for Aid/Watch). However, the High Court could also
be signalling that this kind
of public debate may not be charitable.
One
interpretation might be that this is because the purpose of such a charity would
not be within the spirit and intendment of the
preamble to the Statute
of Charitable Uses. However, it is difficult to infer this
because the majority failed to refer at all to the preamble, despite classifying
Aid/Watch
as falling within the fourth head. It may be simply that the
requirement was satisfied because Aid/Watch was generating debate concerning
a
recognised Pemsel head, but it is not entirely clear. Further, there are
authorities suggesting that the general purposes of government may be
charitable.[251] If
this authority is accepted, the Statute of Charitable
Uses requirement would be superfluous.
The real difficulty, however,
in determining the extent of the ruling in Aid/Watch lies in the fact
that the High Court judgment does not clearly indicate whether the ‘public
benefit’ lies primarily in
the generation of public debate itself, in the
charitable purpose which is being publicly debated, or in some combination of
the
two.
In one view, the public benefit largely arises out of the charitable
purpose itself, and public debate is in a sense ancillary to
this public
benefit. Such a view may justify restricting the application of Aid/Watch
to public debate concerning identified charitable purposes. A much broader view
is that the public benefit resides in the public
debate itself, inhering in the
value of political speech in a democratic and pluralistic society. As noted
earlier, this view would
relieve courts from adjudicating on the merits of any
particular viewpoint.
The trouble with the first view is that the High Court
did not characterise public debate as a means of achieving the purpose of
relieving poverty, but rather considered that the generation of lawful debate
was in itself a purpose
beneficial to the community. Further, that view does not
sit easily with High Court’s discussion of the implied freedom of
political communication. Yet the majority judgment also falls well short of
describing political speech as inherently of public benefit;
instead it
emphasises that the implied freedom arises as a necessary incident of a
constitutional system that provides for elections
and
referenda,[252] and
restricts the ratio to topics already recognised as
charitable.[253]
The
compromise reached by the High Court may well mean that while there is general
value in political speech, the context of that
speech is also important in
determining the ‘public benefit’ of that public debate. This may
well be the route by which
the judges grapple with the thorny questions of how,
absent a political purposes doctrine, charity law might deal with (for example)
racist societies and organisations devoted to the repeal of anti-discrimination
legislation — examples raised in the oral
hearing,[254] but
not addressed in the judgment.
Ultimately, these various uncertainties stem
from the absence of a clear rationale in the majority judgment. While the judges
pointed
to the constitutional assumption of the public benefit of political
debate, its connection with the majority’s conclusions
was curiously
oblique. Perhaps this reflects a reluctance to engage more fully with the
controversial doctrine of the implied freedom
of political communication
because, despite referring to the implied freedom repeatedly during the hearing,
the judgment fails to
draw upon the relevant jurisprudence.
The absence of a
clear rationale can also be partly attributed to the conservative line adopted
by Aid/Watch in the hearing. In shying
away from the more ambitious claim about
the public benefit of public debate, and the ‘functional’ argument
based on
the intimate relationship between charity and politics, counsel missed
an opportunity to set out a more compelling or broader rationale.
Indeed,
although the High Court decision is a fitting successor to the liberalising
charity law decisions in Central Bayside General
Practice Association Ltd v Commissioner
of State Revenue
(Vic)[255] in
2006 and Federal Commissioner of
Taxation v Word Investments
Ltd[256] in
2008, it also represents a missed opportunity. The majority did not address the
supposed rationales justifying the political purposes
doctrine, nor did it
reject the false dichotomy of charity and politics. More importantly, the Court
failed to articulate a clear
vision of the role of politics in charity, a vision
in which it is an important and sometimes essential part of the mission of
charities
to criticise and influence legislation and government policy; in which
charities’ participation in public debate enriches public
discourse and
government decision-making; and in which charities, as well as governments, have
a primary role of driving and fostering
social change.
Importantly, such a
vision fits well with other principles of public law. It invokes public law
norms of participation and consultation,
and builds upon ideals of deliberative
decision-making and public engagement in decision-making. Further, charities
promote the key
public law norms of accountability and transparency by acting as
a watchdog of government and of business. Ultimately, such a vision
is grounded
upon contemporary theories and conceptions of democracy and lawmaking that
better reflect the complexity of modern governance.
VII REFLECTION 3: THE HOLE IN THE HEART
These reflections on the
Aid/Watch case ultimately support Parachin’s conclusion that there
is a hole in the heart of charity law — namely the absence of
a conception
of ‘charity’
itself.[257] The
different decisions in Aid/Watch reflect, at heart, different views about
the appropriate role and nature of charity. Implicitly, the majority of the High
Court endorsed
a progressive view of charity which recognised the legitimacy of
charitable advocacy and, further, the legitimacy of the form of
advocacy
undertaken by Aid/Watch.
In contrast, Heydon J endorsed a narrow traditional
conception, in which poverty is relieved by direct distribution of aid and
short-term
increases of material prosperity, and education takes the rarefied
form of debating societies. Although Kiefel J formally embraced
a more
progressive role for charity, she struggled with the idea that charities could
achieve public benefit merely by ‘talking’
about
issues.
Similarly, while the Full Federal Court broadly construed the
environmental and social justice policies of Aid/Watch as ‘relieving
poverty’, and considered the publication of research reports a legitimate
form of ‘education’, the judges struggled
with the idea of
‘campaigning’ charities. Perhaps the AAT came closest to
articulating a modern vision of charity, most
clearly in a passage where
Downes J, after referring to extensive changes in administrative practice
and law promoting public engagement
and consultation, said:
Rules established a century ago relating to what is charitable need to be revisited in this light. If seeking to influence government to deliver more effective aid may improve the quality of the aid, may that not be charitable? If it is government policy to furnish aid to less developed countries, why would seeking to increase or redirect the aid not be charitable because the purpose is political? Why would similar considerations not apply to protection of the environment? If there was a time when robust attempts to influence government policy could not themselves be charitable, is that still the position?[258]
These
underlying disagreements about the real nature of ‘charity’ have
bedevilled charity law. Several puzzles can be
identified in this debate. First,
when does a charity stop being a private organisation for the public benefit
because it is too
closely intertwined with government or business (the
‘demarcation’ debate)? Second, to what extent should purposes that
are not popularly regarded as charitable (for example, the purposes of an opera
company or a private school) be considered ‘charitable’
in law (the
‘popular versus legal’ definition debate)? Third, when is an
organisation promoting its own private interests
rather than the public interest
(the ‘public benefit’ debate)? Fourth, to what extent is
‘charity’ a progressive
or conservative vision (the
‘ideological’ debate)? The final question, which underlies the other
debates, is what, exactly,
is the ‘good’ in charity?
Some
insights into these puzzles are sketched here, although it is beyond the scope
of this article to address them comprehensively.
The aim is to probe what these
puzzles reveal about our deeply held conceptions of charity, and to suggest
what, exactly, is the
‘good’ in charity.
A The ‘Demarcation’ Debate
As already discussed,
there have been remarkable historical shifts in the relationships between the
three ‘sectors’ of
public life (government, business and the
not-for-profit sector). As charities have become more reliant on government
funding and
commercial partnerships, these entanglements reshape the nature of
the charitable sector and confound traditional expectations of
charities.
These anxieties suggest an ‘ideal-type’ charity,
namely an organisation established and run by private individuals for
the
community out of pure altruism. In part, therefore, what distinguishes the
charitable sector is that the driving force of action
is this element of
voluntarism or altruism, as the Sheppard Inquiry
identified.[259] In
contrast, the driving force of an ‘ideal-type’ government is the
obligation to serve the public welfare, and that
of an ‘ideal-type’
business is self-interest in the form of profit. Part of the reason we value and
support the charitable
sector, therefore, is consensus on the moral value of
selflessness and other-regarding behaviour, and (perhaps) our recognition that
this moral impulse is weak in humans and requires encouragement. At least one
element of the concept of charity, therefore, resides
in the distinctive value
of its form. This resonates with the literature identifying the
‘process benefits’ of charities, such as political pluralism,
superior
efficiency, promotion of individual freedom, and autonomy from
government.[260]
The demarcation debate also reveals that the ways we think about charity are
historically, socially and politically determined. Hospitals
were originally
charitable because they were considered institutions for the
poor;[261] but in a
context where private hospitals compete with not-for-profit hospitals, the
tax-exempt status of hospitals has come under
fire.[262]
Similarly, newspapers, once highly profitable, are now increasingly becoming
not-for-profit as their attached advertising businesses
have
dwindled.[263] A
classic marker of when government or not-for-profit provision is necessary is
when such goods will not be provided by the market,
and this aspect has been
very influential in the economic tradition of not-for-profit theory in the
US.[264]
What
this suggests is that there are four dominant mechanisms (government, business,
the not-for-profit sector and the household sector)
which produce all
‘goods’ (in the broadest sense). What we think of as
‘naturally’ falling within each domain
depends upon economic,
technological, social and political conditions. What is inherently
‘charitable’, therefore, resides
less in the type of good than in
the form of provision. This helps explain puzzles such as when economic
development activities can
be considered ‘charitable’. While
classically economic goods seem to fall within the natural domain of the market,
they
may well be ‘charitable’ under some circumstances, such as the
provision of banking services or utilities in a community
otherwise
without.[265]
Yet
economic theory tends to assume that the market is the most effective mechanism
of provision, all else being equal, and both government
and not-for-profit
provision merely ‘compensate’ for market
deficiencies.[266]
This is not historically accurate and also tends to assume as
‘normal’ what are in reality rather special conditions
for the
effective operation of a competitive
market.[267] An
alternative, ‘mixed systems’, approach posits instead that while
each sector has a natural ‘domain’, they
also operate to supplement
each other, providing compensatory and competitive mechanisms for producing
‘goods’. This
approach displaces the primacy of the market paradigm,
and instead ‘mixed systems’ are seen as necessary to provide optimal
outcomes for all. One example in which a ‘mixed systems’ perspective
is relevant is in the vexed question of whether
tax concessions distort the even
playing field of
capitalism.[268]
B The ‘Popular versus Legal’ Debate
Another puzzle is the
disjuncture between the relief of poverty and other legally charitable objects.
Early proposals to redefine
the definition of charity focused on restricting the
meaning to the relief of poverty or
disadvantage,[269]
and others have proposed a ‘moral hierarchy’ of charity in
determining access to tax
benefits.[270] In
large part, this disjuncture reflects the historical origins of charity, which
arose primarily in the context of relief of poverty.
Even the advancement of
education historically reflected a concern with
poverty.[271]
This disjuncture has been best explained by the Ontario Law Reform
Commission (‘OLRC’) in its final report on
charities.[272] The
OLRC argued that the ‘real’ nature of charity is comprised of two
key elements: (i) doing good (ii) for
others.[273] In
defining ‘good’, the OLRC referred to a conception of ultimate human
goods, such as knowledge and play, that has been
set out in the work of the
philosopher John
Finnis.[274] This
treats matters such as spirituality, art, knowledge and the like as ends rather
than means.
In the OLRC’s view, the distinction between the
‘popular’ and ‘legal’ definition of charity reflects
a
distinction between the degree of deprivation and the means of
flourishing.[275]
This interpretation suggests a distinction between, on the one hand, redressing
disadvantage, and on the other, enriching individuals
and communities in largely
non-economic dimensions of human experience and life. However, the
‘legal’ concept of charity
is united by the fact that both aspects
are aimed at the full flourishing of individuals and the communities to which
they belong.
This analysis sheds light on some of the puzzles of charity law.
For example, the ‘popular’ understanding of charity as
concerned
with poverty can be readily generalised into a broader concern with redressing
disadvantage. This helps explain the case
of Public
Trustee[276]
and the case of Victorian Women Lawyers’
Association,[277]
both of which recognised as charitable bodies that were, at heart, addressing
societal disadvantages. It is that concern which would
distinguish such bodies
from, for example, a white supremacist
group.[278]
Further, the OLRC’s analysis sheds light on the traditional
distinction between sport and charity. It is accepted doctrine that,
in certain
conditions, sporting activity can be charitable, especially where it is designed
to address disadvantage. Yet sporting
activity per se is not charitable, being
of private interest
only.[279] If we
accept the OLRC’s analysis, however, sport can also be theorised as
promoting the ultimate good of ‘play’
alongside its incidental
by-products, such as promoting community life and health.
C The ‘Public Benefit’ Debate
The OLRC’s
two-part definition also helps elucidate the public benefit debate. In defining
‘others’, the OLRC employed
a concept of ‘obligational
distance’, in which the good was performed for the benefit of those to
whom no real obligation
is owed (unlike for example a family or
friend).[280] This
definition imports therefore the crucial element of altruism as part of the
‘good’ of charity.
This element also makes sense of the puzzle in
charity law about what constitutes the ‘public’ for the purposes of
analysing
public benefit. The more remote the beneficiary is from any
obligational relationship, the more clearly ‘public’ the
organisation is. Indicia used in the case law such as geographical criteria, the
openness of the group, and the size of the group
act as proxies for this element
of obligational
distance.[281] The
‘public’ requirement, therefore, is intimately linked to the moral
value of other-regarding behaviour.
D The Ideological Debate
The debate over the
definition of charity is in large part an ideological debate. Chesterman’s
critique of charity
law[282] reflected
perhaps the high noon of progressive belief in the welfare state. The
19th century, in contrast, conceived of charity law in
a moralistic, individualistic fashion that would be considered regressive
today.[283] This
ideological debate underlies Aid/Watch’s claim that it ‘believe[s]
in solidarity not
charity’.[284]
Charity can play both sides of the political fence. The UK Labour Government
spent considerable political energy on reforming charities
and championing their
voice; the succeeding coalition government has championed charities as the heart
of the ‘Big
Society’.[285]
To some extent, this reflects the contemporary consensus that neither government
nor the market is necessarily a ‘first-best’
option, as well as
shifting practices which encourage integration between the three sectors. To
some extent, it also reflects a political
enthusiasm on both sides of the fence
to slim down government, empower citizens and generate a sense of community and
self-empowerment,
in part to counter widespread cynicism and political apathy.
The values that can be ascribed to charity are many and various, and
come close
to representing a modern political consensus — for example, deliberative
democracy, political participation and
engagement, devolved decision-making,
individual empowerment and autonomy, social capital, civil society, and the
downsizing of government.
What is also good about charity, then, is that it
represents the ‘liberal’ sphere in a liberal democracy —
‘society’
as opposed to ‘the state’ or even ‘its
citizens’, a mode of human interaction that is foundational to, yet
distinct from, a polity.
VIII CONCLUSION
When we think about what
is ‘good’ about charity, several threads of thought can be
distinguished. First, one facet of
‘charity’ relates to valuable
dimensions of human experience and life which are not easily quantified or
assimilated
into the public sphere or the market. Second, another facet reflects
a concern with deprivation and disadvantage. Third, ‘charity’
also
reflects the moral value of other-regarding and altruistic behaviour. This is
more important than the type of good produced,
although charity frequently
provides under-served goods which itself is a valuable benefit. Finally, the
value of ‘charity’
can also be interpreted as grounded in its
promotion of liberal attributes, which are foundational to a healthy and vibrant
society
and democracy.
These threads provide us with some guideposts on the
way to locating the ‘good’ (or, more likely, multiple goods) of
charity,
and sketch out some broad contours to the concept of charity. Broad as
these contours are, these threads help us to think through
some of the puzzles
of charity law, and identify the policy which charitable privileges and tax
concessions aim to promote.
It also helps us put the ‘hard cases’
posed by the judges in Aid/Watch in context. Arguably, examples such as
racist societies are not ‘hard’ because they conflict with our ideas
of charity,
but rather because they conflict with core political norms, such as
fundamental principles of equality and non-discrimination, as
Drassinower
suggests.[286] These
cases could be accommodated by pre-existing doctrine, such as the rules relating
to illegality, public policy, or public benefit.
An alternative approach would
recognise the privileges of charity as being founded on the key role charity
plays in sustaining our
liberal democracy and society. Such an approach would
logically require basic coherence between core political norms and charitable
objects, while preserving a great deal of latitude for organisations to define
other goods and means of achieving charitable objects.
Finally, our
conception of ‘charity’ can be refined through cross-fertilisation
with public law theory, as suggested above.
Importantly, crucial distinctions
can be made within the categories of ‘politics’ and
‘public’, which are
neither self-explanatory nor indivisible. For
example, it is possible to distinguish at the core of the
‘political’ the
concept of ‘party political’. Party
politics is most visibly manifested not only in political parties but also, in a
Westminster system, in Parliament and the executive. There may well be a useful
distinction between these institutions and the manifold
institutions of
‘government’, which now extends to the most petty of
bureaucracies.
Further, more thinking can be done about the overlapping
‘public’ nature of charities and government in the context of
devolved service delivery. Much discussion has occurred, for example, in the
analogous realm of the scope of the Human Rights Act
1998 (UK) c 42, in the context of the key phrase ‘functions of a
public nature’, along with the more traditional sphere of
judicial
review.[287]
There
is also much to be said for more careful distinctions between the
‘private’ and ‘public’ aspects of
charity, so that (for
example) respect for the ‘private’ origins and institutional form of
charity should encourage courts
to respect organisations’ private
definitions of the public good and their means for achieving it. Some of the
‘public’
aspects of charity, such as the potential to harm the
public and the potential for fraud or misconduct, are more appropriately
addressed
by targeted regulation.
Another aspect of public law that may
enrich charity law is the use of human rights norms to mark out appropriate
limits to freedom
of expression. For example, qualifications to the freedom of
expression such as respect for the rights or reputations of others,
and
countervailing provisions such as the obligation to prohibit ‘advocacy of
national, racial or religious
hatred’,[288]
provide insights into why we object to conferring charitable status on racist or
discriminatory societies — namely, because
of the requirements of
other fundamental liberal principles. Such an analysis accords with
Drassinower’s analysis of the levels
of fundamental political agreement
and the conditions of ‘legality’, discussed above.
Finally, there
is much to be learnt from recent debate in public law about the institutional
and constitutional competence of judges,
since the political purposes doctrine
is ultimately grounded on a claim that is familiar to public
lawyers — the need for judicial
restraint. Scholars have sought to
identify the factors that affect both the institutional and constitutional
competence of judges
to make decisions. For example, Kavanagh has theorised that
a decision-maker should be granted substantial deference only when the
judge
recognises ‘institutional shortcomings’, such as a deficit of
institutional competence, expertise or institutional
or democratic legitimacy,
or where there are prudential reasons to
defer.[289] King has
elaborated a ‘contextual institutional approach’, which is grounded
on a concept of the inter-institutional
comity of, and collaboration between,
branches of government, and identifies at least four general principles of
restraint or deference,
to be applied in context and when relevant:
polycentricity, expertise, flexibility and democratic
legitimacy.[290]
These approaches use principles to structure judicial decision-making that
require careful identification of the particular features
of a decision that
demand deference, in contrast to the crude ‘all-or-nothing’
political purposes doctrine. Applying
these principles makes some sense of the
concern about ‘party political purposes’. Determining the
‘public benefit’
of party politics is likely to pose institutional
problems in determining ‘benefit’ and, importantly, is more likely
to implicate democratic legitimacy. Yet, rather than a black-and-white rule, the
principles of restraint need to be applied after
a careful consideration of all
the facts and the particular context — what Santow J was doubtless
referring to when he suggested
that not all causes were ‘automatically
“political”’.[291]
IX POSTSCRIPT
Since this article was prepared for publication, the Australian government has announced an ambitious agenda for reform of not-for-profits, including a statutory definition of charity to be introduced in 2013 to be administered by a new Commonwealth regulator for charities and not-for-profits, the Australian Charities and Not-for-Profits Commission.[292] The Australian government issued a consultation paper on the statutory definition in late 2011[293] and intends to issue an exposure draft of the statutory definition in early 2012.
[*] BA (Hons), LLB (Hons) (Melb), PhD (UCL); Research Fellow, Melbourne Law School, The University of Melbourne.
[†] BA (Hons), LLB (Hons) (Melb), BCL, DPhil (Oxon); Associate Professor, Melbourne Law School, The University of Melbourne.
[‡] BA (Hons), LLB (Hons), LLM (Melb); Professor, Melbourne Law School, The University of Melbourne; Special Counsel, Allens Arthur Robinson.
[1] [2010] HCA 42; (2010) 241 CLR 539.
[2] Pro Bono Australia, Aid/Watch Decision a Win for Charities’ Freedom of Speech (2 December 2010) Pro Bono News <http://www.probonoaustralia.com.au/news/2010/12/aidwatch-decision-win-charities%E2%80%99-freedom-speech> .
[3] There are other benefits: see generally G E Dal Pont, Law of Charity (LexisNexis Butterworths, 2010) 156–7 [7.18]–[7.20].
[4] However, savings legislation empowers courts to ‘sever’ charitable purposes from non-charitable purposes, therefore preserving to some extent purpose trusts that would otherwise have failed: see ibid 331–9 [13.32]–[13.47].
[5] See generally ibid 129–33 [6.1]–[6.7].
[6] See generally Productivity Commission, ‘Contribution of the Not-for-Profit Sector’ (Research Report, January 2010) app E <http://www.pc.gov.au/projects/study/not-for-profit/report> .
[7] Income Tax Assessment Act 1997 (Cth) ss 50-5, 50-52, sub-div 50-B; A New Tax System (Goods and Services Tax) Act 1999 (Cth) ss 176-1, 176-5; Fringe Benefits Tax Assessment Act 1986 (Cth) pt XA.
[8] Income Tax Assessment Act 1997 (Cth) s 30-45; Fringe Benefits Tax Assessment Act 1986 (Cth) s 57A. See Ann O’Connell, ‘The Tax Position of Charities in Australia — Why Does It Have to Be So Complicated?’ (2008) 37 Australian Tax Review 17.
[9] Commissioners for Special Purposes of the Income Tax v Pemsel [1891] UKHL 1; [1891] AC 531; Chesterman v Federal Commissioner of Taxation [1925] UKPCHCA 2; (1925) 37 CLR 317. The latter case followed the former in holding that the common law meaning of charity governed the term ‘charitable institution’ in Australian income tax legislation, despite an argument that the compound phrase ‘charitable institution’ indicated a narrower meaning.
[10] This has led
to several suggestions that the definition in tax law ought to be
‘decoupled’ from that in the common law:
see, eg, Geoffrey Cross,
‘Some Recent Developments in the Law of Charity’ (1956) 72
Law Quarterly Review 187, 204; Nigel P Gravells,
‘Public Purpose Trusts’ (1977) 40 Modern Law
Review 397; Susan Bright, ‘Charity and Trusts for the Public
Benefit — Time for a Re-Think?’ [1989] Conveyancer
and Property Lawyer 28; John D Colombo and Mark A Hall,
The Charitable Tax Exemption (Westview Press, 1995)
39; G E Dal Pont, ‘Why Define “Charity”? Is the
Search for Meaning Worth the Effort?’
(2002) 8(1) Third
Sector Review 5. See generally Nuzhat Malik, ‘Defining
“Charity” and “Charitable Purposes” in the United
Kingdom’
(2008) 11 International Journal of
Not-for-Profit Law 36
<http://www.icnl.org/
knowledge/ijnl/vol11iss1/special_2.htm>.
[11] See generally Joyce Chia et al, ‘Defining Charity: A Literature Review’ (Not-for-Profit Project, Melbourne Law School, 20 February 2011) <http://tax.law.unimelb.edu.au/go/research-and-resources/current-research-projects/index.cfm> .
[12] See especially Ian Sheppard, Robert Fitzgerald and David Gonski, Report of the Inquiry into the Definition of Charities and Related Organisations (2001) (‘Sheppard Report’).
[13] Instead, the government passed legislation clarifying the charitable status of three particular groups: Extension of Charitable Purpose Act 2004 (Cth). This followed opposition to an exposure draft Bill which purported to entrench the political purposes doctrine into statute: see Charities Bill (Exposure Draft) 2003 (Cth); Board of Taxation, Consultation on the Definition of a Charity: A Report to the Treasurer (2003).
[14] Charities and Trustee Investment (Scotland) Act 2005 (Scot) asp 10, s 7; Charities Act 2006 (UK) c 50, s 2; Charities Act (Northern Ireland) 2008 (NI) c 12, s 2; Charities Act 2009 (Ireland) s 3.
[15] The Treasury (Cth), Final Report: Scoping Study for a National Not-for-Profit Regulator (2011).
[16] Commissioners for Special Purposes of the Income Tax v Pemsel [1891] UKHL 1; [1891] AC 531. The classification appears to have been adopted from counsel’s suggestion in Morice v Bishop of Durham [1804] EngR 179; [1804] 9 Ves 399; 32 ER 656. See Gareth Jones, History of the Law of Charity 1532–1827 (Cambridge University Press, 1969) 124.
[17] The activities of an organisation are relevant in three main circumstances: where there are no rules or constitution; where the rules or constitution do not clearly indicate the organisation’s main objects; or where there is doubt whether the objects reflect the true purposes of the organisation (Dal Pont, Law of Charity, above n 3, 322–3 [13.19]).
[18] The Ontario Law Reform Commission (‘OLRC’) suggested that the test of public benefit comprises three elements, including whether there was sufficient practical utility in the organisation’s purposes: OLRC, Report on the Law of Charities (1996) vol 1, 166.
[19] These purposes were: the relief of the aged, poor and impotent; the maintenance of sick and maimed soldiers and mariners; the repair of bridges, ports, havens, causeways, churches, seabanks and highways; the maintenance of schools and colleges; the education and preferment of orphans; the relief, stock or maintenance of houses of correction; marriages of poor maids; the supportation, aid and help for young tradesmen, handicraftsmen and persons decayed; the relief or redemption of prisoners or captives; and the aid and ease of any poor inhabitants concerning payment of fifteens, setting out soldiers, and other taxes.
[20] Dal Pont, Law of Charity, above n 3, 72–5 [3.46]–[3.52].
[21] [1917] AC 406, 442.
[22] [1947] UKHL 4; [1948] AC 31.
[23] [1982] 1 Ch 321, 340 (Slade J).
[24] Re Hopkinson; Lloyds Bank Ltd v Baker [1949] 1 All ER 346, 350 (Vaisey J).
[25] See, eg, Public Trustee v A-G (NSW) (1997) 42 NSWLR 600, 608 (Santow J). The ATO, however, adopted this proposition in its previous Ruling: ATO, Income Tax and Fringe Benefits Tax: Charities, TR 2005/21, 21 December 2005, 29 [107]–[108]. This Ruling has now been replaced with a new Ruling that reflects the decision in Aid/Watch: ATO, Income Tax and Fringe Benefits Tax: Charities, TR 2011/4, 12 October 2011, 16–17 [70]–[73].
[26] See, eg, Public Trustee v A-G (NSW) (1997) 42 NSWLR 600; A-G (NSW) v The NSW Henry George Foundation Ltd [2002] NSWSC 1128 (27 November 2002).
[27] [1938] HCA 39; (1938) 60 CLR 396.
[28] Ibid 412–13 (Latham CJ), 419 (Rich J), 420 (Starke J), 426–7 (Dixon J).
[29] Ibid 419 (Rich J).
[30] Ibid 412 (Latham CJ).
[31] Ibid 419 (Rich J).
[32] See the discussion in Public Trustee v A-G (NSW) (1997) 42 NSWLR 600, 607–8 (Santow J).
[33] Royal North Shore [1938] HCA 39; (1938) 60 CLR 396, 412.
[34] Ibid 426.
[35] Ibid.
[36] Ibid.
[37] Ibid 427.
[38] Ibid.
[40] [2002] NSWSC 1128 (27 November 2002).
[41] [2008] FCA 983; (2008) 170 FCR 318.
[42] Public Trustee (1997) 42 NSWLR 600, 608.
[43] Ibid 607–8. This view was developed in Justice G F K Santow, ‘Charity in Its Political Voice — A Tinkling Cymbal or a Sounding Brass?’ (1999) 18 Australian Bar Review 225.
[44] [2002] NSWSC 1128 (27 November 2002) [50]–[54], [61]–[64].
[45] [2008] FCA 983; (2008) 170 FCR 318, 348 [128].
[46] Royal North Shore [1938] HCA 39; (1938) 60 CLR 396, 412.
[47] Charities Act 2006 (UK) c 50, s 2(2)(h). Equivalent provisions are found in Charities and Trustee Investment (Scotland) Act 2005 (Scot) asp 10, ss 7(2)(j)–(l); Charities Act (Northern Ireland) 2008 (NI) c 12, s 2(2)(h).
[48] Charity Commission, Speaking Out: Guidance on Campaigning and Political Activity by Charities (2008). Cf, eg, the criticisms in Francis Gladstone, Charity, Law and Social Justice (Bedford Square Press, 1982) 110–14.
[49] Charities Act 2009 (Ireland) ss 3(11)(e)–(f).
[50] Ibid s 2 (definition of ‘excluded body’). However, while the doctrine appears to have been received into Irish law, it has never been litigated: Law Society of Ireland Law Reform Committee, Charity Law: The Case for Reform (2002) 79–80.
[51] Paul Michell, ‘The Political Purposes Doctrine in Canadian Charities Law’ (1995) 12(4) Philanthropist 3, 13.
[52] Income Tax Act, RSC 1985 (5th Supp), c 1, ss 149(6.1)–(6.2). This deems charitable organisations and foundations to include those devoting part of their resources to political activities, where such activities are ‘ancillary and incidental’ to the charitable purposes and do not include direct or indirect support of, or opposition to, any political party or candidate for public office. These provisions were introduced in 1986 as beneficial legislation, intended to recognise the appropriateness of ancillary political expenditure: Terrance S Carter and Theresa L M Man, ‘Charities Speaking Out: The Evolution of Advocacy and Political Activities by Charities in Canada’ (Paper presented at Nonprofit Speech in the 21st Century: Time for a Change?, New York University School of Law National Centre on Philanthropy and the Law, 29 October 2010) <http://www.carters.ca/pub/article/charity/2010/tsc1029.pdf> . The legislation also excludes expenditure on political activities from the disbursement quotas imposed on Canadian charities, but these quotas have recently been reformed: Donald Bourgeois, ‘Eliminating the Disbursement Quota: Gold or Fool’s Gold?’ (2010) 23(2) Philanthropist 184.
[53] Canada Revenue Agency, Policy Statement — Political Activities (2 September 2003) <http://www.cra-arc.gc.ca/chrts-gvng/chrts/plcy/cps/cps-022-eng.html> .
[54] Ibid [6.2].
[55] The activities must also be well-reasoned, cannot be primarily emotive and cannot contain information that the charity knows or ought to know is false, inaccurate or misleading: ibid [7.1]–[7.3].
[56] Ibid [9].
[57] The case law is discussed in L A Sheridan, ‘The Political Muddle — A Charitable View?’ (1977) 19 Malaya Law Review 42.
[58] Note, ‘Charitable Trusts for Political Purposes’ (1951) 37 Virginia Law Review 988, 989.
[59] 116 A 826, 828 (Frazer J for Frazer, Walling, Simpson, Kephart and Sadler JJ) (Pa, 1922).
[60] The US law is quite complex. See generally Bruce R Hopkins, Charity, Advocacy, and the Law: How Nonprofit Organizations Can Use Charitable Dollars to Affect Public Policy — Lawfully (John Wiley & Sons, 1992).
[61] For discussion of this restriction, see, eg, Elias Clark, ‘The Limitation on Political Activities: A Discordant Note in the Law of Charities’ (1960) 46 Virginia Law Review 439; Ronald S Borod, ‘Lobbying for the Public Interest — Federal Tax Policy and Administration’ (1967) 42 New York University Law Review 1087; Note, ‘The Revenue Code and a Charity’s Politics’ (1964) 73 Yale Law Journal 661; Mortimer M Caplin and Richard E Timbie, ‘Legislative Activities of Public Charities’ (1975) 39(4) Law and Contemporary Problems 183; Note, ‘The Tax Code’s Differential Treatment of Lobbying under Section 501(c)(3): A Proposed First Amendment Analysis’ (1980) 66 Virginia Law Review 1513; Laura B Chisolm, ‘Exempt Organization Advocacy: Matching the Rules to the Rationales’ (1988) 63 Indiana Law Journal 201; Richard L Haight, ‘Lobbying for the Public Good: Limitations on Legislative Activities by Section 501(c)(3) Organizations’ (1988) 23 Gonzaga Law Review 77.
[62] IRC § 501(h) (2006). The legislative history of these restrictions is described extensively in several works, including Oliver A Houck, ‘On the Limits of Charity: Lobbying, Litigation, and Electoral Politics by Charitable Organizations under the Internal Revenue Code and Related Laws’ (2003) 69 Brooklyn Law Review 1, 8–37.
[63] For discussion of this restriction, see, eg, Laura Brown Chisolm, ‘Politics and Charity: A Proposal for Peaceful Coexistence’ (1990) 58 George Washington Law Review 308; Johnny Rex Buckles, ‘Not Even a Peep? The Regulation of Political Campaign Activity by Charities through Federal Tax Law’ (2007) 75 University of Cincinnati Law Review 1071.
[64] Office of the Scottish Charity Regulator, Meeting the Charity Test: Guidance for Applicants and for Existing Charities (2010) [5.3]. The legislation does, however, disqualify political parties and organisations with a purpose of advancing a political party: Charities and Trustee Investment (Scotland) Act 2005 (Scot) asp 10, s 7(4)(c).
[65] ‘Non-governmental organisations’ is defined to exclude political parties: Committee of Ministers, Council of Europe, Recommendation on the Legal Status of Non-Governmental Organisations in Europe, Recommendation CM/Rec(2007)14 (10 October 2007) [1].
[66] Ibid [12].
[67] Ibid [13].
[68] Ibid [57].
[69] For a comprehensive review, see Chia et al, above n 11.
[70] The authorities were based on the public policy doctrine. This criticism was accepted in National Anti-Vivisection Society [1947] UKHL 4; [1948] AC 31, 54 (Lord Porter), 63 (Lord Simonds).
[71] Michael Chesterman, Charities, Trusts and Social Welfare (Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1979) 181–3.
[72] See generally Adam Parachin, ‘Distinguishing Charity and Politics: The Judicial Thinking behind the Doctrine of Political Purposes’ (2008) 45 Alberta Law Review 871, 880–97.
[73] Bowman [1917] AC 406, 442 (Lord Parker).
[74] National Anti-Vivisection Society [1947] UKHL 4; [1948] AC 31, 50 (Lord Wright). This passage cites Amherst D Tyssen, The Law of Charitable Bequests: With an Account of the Mortmain and Charitable Uses Act, 1888 (William Clowes and Sons, 1888) 177.
[75] Royal North Shore [1938] HCA 39; (1938) 60 CLR 396, 426 (Dixon J).
[76] National Anti-Vivisection Society [1947] UKHL 4; [1948] AC 31, 50 (Lord Wright), 62 (Lord Simonds). See also McGovern v A-G [1982] 1 Ch 321, 337 (Slade J).
[77] See Abraham Drassinower, ‘The Doctrine of Political Purposes in the Law of Charities: A Conceptual Analysis’ in Jim Phillips, Bruce Chapman, and David Stevens (eds), Between State and Market: Essays on Charities Law and Policy in Canada (McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2001) 288, 293–4.
[78] L A Sheridan, ‘Charity versus Politics’ (1973) 2 Anglo-American Law Review 47; Kate Tokeley, ‘A New Definition for Charity?’ (1991) 21 Victoria University of Wellington Law Review 41, 51; Santow, above n 43, 229; Advisory Group on Campaigning and the Voluntary Sector, Report (2007) 11–14 [0.5.4]–[0.6.6] <http://www.ncvo-vol.org.uk/regulation-legislation> .
[79] L A Sheridan, ‘Charitable Causes, Political Causes and Involvement’ (1980) 2(4) Philanthropist 5, 12.
[80] See, eg, ibid 12; Parachin, above n 72, 880.
[81] Lord Woolf, Jeffrey Jowell and Andrew Le Sueur, De Smith’s Judicial Review (Sweet & Maxwell, 6th ed, 2007) ch 4.
[82] See, eg, Phillip Coorey, ‘Rights Bill May Corrupt Judiciary, Says Ex-Judge’, The Sydney Morning Herald (Sydney), 25 May 2009, 9; Michael Pelly, ‘Chief Justice Opposed to Bill of Rights’, The Australian (Sydney), 29 May 2009, 29.
[83] In the US context, see, eg, Wilfred R Caron and Deidre Dessingue, ‘IRC § 501(c)(3): Practical and Constitutional Implications of “Political” Activity Restrictions’ (1985) 2 Journal of Law and Politics 169; Edward McGlynn Gaffney Jr, ‘On Not Rendering to Caesar: The Unconstitutionality of Tax Regulation of Activities of Religious Organizations Relating to Politics’ (1990) 40 DePaul Law Review 1; Erik J Ablin, ‘The Price of Not Rendering to Caesar: Restrictions on Church Participation in Political Campaigns’ (1999) 13 Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics & Public Policy 541, 567–9; Eric R Swibel, ‘Churches and Campaign Intervention: Why the Tax Man Is Right and How Congress Can Improve His Reputation’ (2008) 57 Emory Law Journal 1605.
[84] It has been argued in the US that restrictions on advocacy could violate the equal protection clause of the US Constitution, because businesses are not similarly restricted: see Edward W Wachtel, ‘David Meets Goliath in the Legislative Arena: A Losing Battle for an Equal Charitable Voice?’ (1972) 9 San Diego Law Review 944; Gregory E Robinson, ‘Charitable Lobbying Restraints and Tax Exempt Organizations: Old Problems, New Directions?’ [1984] Utah Law Review 337. This can also be justified on public policy grounds of equality and improving the legislative process: see Alvin J Geske, ‘Direct Lobbying Activities of Public Charities’ (1973) 26 Tax Lawyer 305.
[85] For example, there is a right to participate directly in the conduct of public affairs: International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, opened for signature 16 December 1966, 999 UNTS 171 (entered into force 23 March 1976) art 25(a). It has also been argued in the US that restrictions on advocacy could infringe the right to petition (an implied right): Wachtel, above n 84, 955.
[86] In the US, it has been argued that the political purposes doctrine may infringe the doctrine prohibiting impermissible ‘vagueness’: see Borod, above n 61, 1106; Caplin and Timbie, above n 61, 202–3.
[87] George Cooper, ‘The Tax Treatment of Business Grassroots Lobbying: Defining and Attaining the Public Policy Objectives’ (1968) 68 Columbia Law Review 801, 830–41; John Michael Clear, ‘Political Speech of Charitable Organizations under the Internal Revenue Code’ (1974) 41 University of Chicago Law Review 352; Caplin and Timbie, above n 61, 201–6; Note, ‘The Tax Code’s Differential Treatment’, above n 61; Kay Guinane, ‘Wanted: A Bright-Line Test Defining Prohibited Intervention in Elections by 501(c)(3) Organizations’ (2007) 6 First Amendment Law Review 142, 156–8; Benjamin Vaughn, ‘The High Cost of Free Exercise: All Saints, the Service, and Section 501(c)(3)’ (2008) 61 Tax Lawyer 981.
[88] Cammarano v United States[1959] USSC 23; , 358 US 498, 512–13 (Harlan J for Warren CJ, Black, Frankfurter, Clark, Harlan, Brennan, Whittaker and Stewart JJ), 515 (Douglas J) (1959); Alliance for Life v Minister of National Revenue [1999] 3 FC 504, 558 (Stone JA, Linden and McDonald JJA agreeing); Human Life International in Canada Inc v Minister of National Revenue [1998] 3 FC 202, 220–1 (Strayer JA, Isaac CJ and Robertson JA agreeing).
[89] Committee of Inquiry into the Effect of Charity Law and Practice on Voluntary Organisations, Charity Law and Voluntary Organisations (1976) 45 [103] (‘Goodman Report’).
[90] Myron Walker and Tim Rothermel, ‘Political Activity and Tax Exempt Organizations before and after the Tax Reform Act of 1969’ (1970) 38 George Washington Law Review 1114, 1126; Advisory Group on Campaigning and the Voluntary Sector, above n 78, 20 [0.9.7].
[91] Alison Dunn,
‘Charity Law as a Political Option for the Poor’ (1999) 50
Northern Ireland Legal Quarterly 298, 300; Advisory
Group on Campaigning and the Voluntary Sector, above n 78,
19–20 [0.9.4]–[0.9.6].
[92] Most commentators agree that there is an ‘unacceptable political realm’, even if they reject the current dividing line or the proposed justifications for it: Dunn, ‘Charity Law as a Political Option for the Poor’, above n 91, 307; Parachin, above n 72, 872–3.
[93] Borod, above n 61, 1115. Borod argues for administrative reform along the lines of the original formulation in the US legislation, focusing on the desire to prevent individuals associated with the organisation from turning charity to personal advantage. The ‘private interest theory’ is also discussed by Buckles, ‘Not Even a Peep?’, above n 63, 1085–9.
[94] OLRC, above n 18, 152–4. The Commission expressed the view that the distinction was largely ‘formal’, a distinction between what is being done and why it is being done, and therefore had to be evaluated in an open-textured way.
[95] J Stevens and D J Feldman, ‘Broadcasting Advertisements by Bodies with Political Objects, Judicial Review, and the Influence of Charities Law’ [1997] Public Law 615, 617.
[96] Guinane, above n 87, 167–8. This suggested that genuine advocacy involved three features: (i) a nexus to legislative issues; (ii) no references to an election, candidate, campaign or party; and (iii) no position taken on the qualifications and fitness of a candidate.
[97] See Note, ‘The Revenue Code and a Charity’s Politics’, above n 61, 674–5, especially at 674 n 57; Walker and Rothermel, above n 90, 1135; Ablin, above n 83, 585–6; Richard Bridge, ‘The Law of Advocacy by Charitable Organizations: The Case for Change’ (2002) 21 Estates, Trusts & Pensions Journal 92, 105–6, 116–17.
[98] Cooper, above n 87, 846–50; Kernaghan Webb, Cinderella’s Slippers? The Role of Charitable Tax Status in Financing Canadian Interest Groups (SFU-UBC Centre for the Study of Government and Business, 2000) 117–19.
[99] Senate Standing Committee on Economics, Parliament of Australia, Disclosure Regimes for Charities and Not-for-Profit Organisations (2008) 85 [8.18].
[100] Lynn Lu, ‘Flunking the Methodology Test: A Flawed Tax-Exemption Standard for Educational Organizations That “Advocate a Particular Position or Viewpoint”’ (2004) 29 New York University Review of Law and Social Change 377, 382; Jonathan Garton, The Regulation of Organised Civil Society (Hart Publishing, 2009) 71–5.
[101] Nicola Silke, ‘“Please Sir, May I Have Some More?” Allowing New Zealand Charities a Political Voice’ [2002] CanterLawRw 4; (2002) 8 Canterbury Law Review 345, 364; Parachin, above n 72, 884.
[102] Goodman Report, above n 89, 31 [73]; Tokeley, above n 78, 51; Stevens and Feldman, above n 95, 622.
[103] J Craig Jenkins, ‘Nonprofit Organizations and Political Advocacy’ in Walter W Powell and Richard Steinberg (eds), The Nonprofit Sector: A Research Handbook (Yale University Press, 2nd ed, 2006) 307, 307.
[104] See, eg, ibid; Donald B Tobin, ‘Political Campaigning by Churches and Charities: Hazardous for 501(c)(3)s, Dangerous for Democracy’ (2007) 95 Georgetown Law Journal 1313, 1317–18. This rationale has been especially influential in US case law: see Slee v Commissioner of Internal Revenue, 42 F 2d 184 (2nd Cir, 1930); Cammarano v United States[1959] USSC 23; , 358 US 498 (1959).
[105] Perri 6 and Anita Randon, Liberty, Charity and Politics: Non-Profit Law and Freedom of Speech (Dartmouth Publishing, 1995) 202–3; Jenkins, above n 103, 326.
[106] Clark, above n 61, 456–8; Caplin and Timbie, above n 61, 198–9; Chisolm, ‘Exempt Organization Advocacy’, above n 61, 272–4; Jenkins, above n 103, 326.
[107] Wachtel, above n 84, 958; Bridge, above n 97, 109–10; Advisory Group on Campaigning and the Voluntary Sector, above n 78, 9–10 [0.4.1], 16–17 [0.7.3].
[108] See, eg, Clark, above n 61, 452, who argues that the restrictions target those whose message is ‘aimed at the one agency, government in all its forms, which can effect the most immediate solution to society’s problems’.
[109] See, eg, Caplin and Timbie, above n 61, 196–8; Gladstone, above n 48, ch 7; Bright, above n 10, 34; Dunn, ‘Charity Law as a Political Option for the Poor’, above n 91; Laurie Rektor, ‘Advocacy — The Sound of Citizens’ Voices’ (Position Paper, Advocacy Working Group, Voluntary Sector Initiative, September 2002); Betsy A Harvie, ‘Regulation of Advocacy in the Voluntary Sector: Current Challenges and Some Responses’ (Report, Voluntary Sector Initiative, January 2002) 4–5; Silke, above n 101; Advisory Group on Campaigning and the Voluntary Sector, above n 78, 9–10 [0.4.1]–[0.4.3]; Senate Standing Committee on Economics, above n 99, 84 [8.16].
[110] Clark, above n 61, 454; Borod, above n 61, 1116; Clear, above n 87, 366; Advisory Group on Campaigning and the Voluntary Sector, above n 78, 9–10 [0.4.1].
[111] Harvie, above n 109, 7–9.
[112] A more extreme version is posited as an ‘antithetical agency hypothesis’ by Buckles, ‘Not Even a Peep’, above n 63, 1092–5. This hypothesis suggests that each sector seeks to serve the community entirely separately from each other, so should have no voice in the other sector. Buckles argues that the ‘complementary agency hypothesis’, where state and charity work side by side, better describes the current legal relationship.
[113] See, eg, Ann M Murphy, ‘Campaign Signs and the Collection Plate — Never the Twain Shall Meet?’ (2003) 1 Pittsburgh Tax Review 35, 81; Tobin, above n 104, 1319. This argument is discussed, but not supported, by Parachin, above n 72, 887. Similar arguments have been considered and rejected in relation to churches: see, eg, Steffen N Johnson, ‘Of Politics and Pulpits: A First Amendment Analysis of IRS Restrictions on the Political Activities of Religious Organizations’ (2001) 42 Boston College Law Review 875, 885–7.
[114] This suggestion finds favour in Frances R Hill, ‘Corporate Philanthropy and Campaign Finance: Exempt Organizations as Corporate-Candidate Conduits’ (1997) 41 New York Law School Law Review 881; Murphy, above n 113, 81; Lloyd Hitoshi Mayer, ‘Grasping Smoke: Enforcing the Ban on Political Activity by Charities’ (2007) 6 First Amendment Law Review 1, 6. There is empirical evidence of the potency of this belief in health charities in the UK: Alison Dunn, ‘Hippocratic Oath or Gordian Knot? The Politicisation of Health Care Trustees and Their Role in Campaigning’ (2007) 18 King’s Law Journal 481, 496–7.
[115] In Re Ingram [1951] VicLawRp 62; [1951] VLR 424, it was held that a trust established for the preservation of flora and fauna was for a ‘purpose beneficial to the community’. Campaigns against slavery have been recognised by the Canada Revenue Agency as having the purpose of ‘preserving human life and health’ and therefore being ‘beneficial to the community’: Canada Revenue Agency, Upholding Human Rights and Charitable Registration (15 May 2010) [6.4] <http://www.cra-arc.gc.ca/chrts-gvng/chrts/plcy/cgd/hmn-rghts-eng.html> .
[116] See Harvie, above n 109, 6. This cites a survey showing strong support by Canadians for a range of advocacy activities by charities.
[117] Aid/Watch, Annual Report 2009 (2010) 6.
[118] Samuel D Brunson, ‘Reigning in Charities: Using an Intermediate Penalty to Enforce the Campaigning Prohibition’ (2011) 8 Pittsburgh Tax Review 125, 142. See also Eleanor Burt, ‘Charities and Political Activity: Time to Re-Think the Rules’ (1998) 69 Political Quarterly 23, 28.
[119] This is explored in detail by Drassinower, above n 77. See also Borod, above n 61, 1104–5; Dunn, ‘Charity Law as a Political Option for the Poor’, above n 91.
[120] Chesterman, above n 71, 354–8.
[121] Drassinower, above n 77, 299.
[122] It was incorporated as an association on 26 May 1993 under the Associations Incorporation Act 1984 (NSW): Aid/Watch [2010] HCA 42; (2010) 241 CLR 539, 544 [1] (French CJ, Gummow, Hayne, Crennan and Bell JJ).
[123] Its constitution is available at Aid/Watch, About Aid/Watch <http://aidwatch.org.au/about-aidwatch> .
[124] See Aid/Watch, Annual Report 2009, above n 117.
[125] See Australian Council for International Development, Total Funds Raised by Australian NGOs <http://www.acfid.asn.au/resources/facts-and-figures/total-funds-raised-aust-ngos> .
[126] AusAID,
About Australia’s Aid Program (20 May 2011)
<http://www.ausaid.gov.au/makediff/
default.cfm>.
[127] Australian Council for International Development, above n 125.
[128] AusAID, Accreditation for Non-Government Organisations (18 March 2011) <http://www.ausaid.gov.au/ngos/accreditation.cfm> .
[129] Joel Negin, ‘Reviving Dead Aid: Making International Development Assistance Work’ (Analysis, Lowy Institute for International Policy, August 2010) 15–16.
[130] Ibid 5.
[131] Aid/Watch, About Aid/Watch, above n 123.
[132] Aid/Watch Inc v Federal Commissioner of Taxation [2008] AATA 652 (28 July 2008) [10] (Downes J).
[133] Ibid [11].
[134] Aid/Watch, ‘ATO Decision Has Implications for All Charities’ (Backgrounder, 30 May 2007) <http://aidwatch.org.au/sites/aidwatch.org.au/files/ATO+backgrounger+30th+May+2007.pdf> Aid/Watch, ‘Background on the Aid/Watch Charitable Tax Status Case’ (Backgrounder, 1 October 2009) <http://aidwatch.org.au/sites/aidwatch.org.au/files/AIDWATCH_CourtCaseBackground.pdf> .
[135] Aid/Watch Inc v Federal Commissioner of Taxation [2008] AATA 652 (28 July 2008) [11] (Downes J). The review was sought pursuant to ss 426–60, 14ZL and 14ZZ of the Taxation Administration Act 1953 (Cth).
[136] Aid/Watch Inc v Federal Commissioner of Taxation [2008] AATA 652 (28 July 2008).
[137] Ibid [41].
[138] Ibid [6], [47].
[139] Ibid [23].
[140] Ibid [5].
[141] Ibid [32], [39].
[142] Ibid [40].
[143] Ibid [41].
[144] Ibid [42].
[145] Ibid [6].
[146] Ibid [47].
[147] Ibid [35].
[148] Ibid.
[149] Ibid [21].
[150] Ibid [18]–[21].
[151] Ibid [45].
[152] Ibid [44].
[153] Federal Commissioner of Taxation v Aid/Watch Inc [2009] FCAFC 128; (2009) 178 FCR 423.
[154] Ibid 427 [19] (Kenny, Stone and Perram JJ).
[155] Ibid 427 [18].
[156] Ibid.
[157] Ibid 429 [27]–[28].
[158] Ibid 428 [24].
[159] Ibid 427–8 [20].
[160] Ibid 430 [36].
[161] Ibid 430–1 [37].
[162] Ibid 431 [39]–[40].
[163] Ibid 431 [38], quoting Public Trustee (1997) 42 NSWLR 600, 620.
[164] Federal Commissioner of Taxation v Aid/Watch Inc [2009] FCAFC 128; (2009) 178 FCR 423, 431–2 [41] (Kenny, Stone and Perram JJ).
[165] Ibid 432 [43]–[45].
[166] Ibid 432 [45].
[167] Ibid 433 [47].
[168] Transcript of Proceedings, Aid/Watch Inc v Federal Commissioner of Taxation [2010] HCATrans 154 (15 June 2010); Transcript of Proceedings, Aid/Watch Inc v Federal Commissioner of Taxation [2010] HCATrans 155 (16 June 2010).
[169] Interestingly, Heydon J queried this reliance on the presumption, observing that there was ‘very fragile support in authority’ for it: Transcript of Proceedings, Aid/Watch Inc v Federal Commissioner of Taxation [2010] HCATrans 154 (15 June 2010) 2601.
[170] Ibid 216–24, 1102–7 (D L Williams SC).
[171] Ibid 187–90 (French CJ).
[172] As suggested by French CJ in ibid 124.
[173] Ibid 97–106 (D L Williams SC).
[174] Ibid 1085–94 (Crennan J and D L Williams SC).
[175] Ibid 2327–54, 2492–7 (D M J Bennett QC).
[176] Transcript of Proceedings, Aid/Watch Inc v Federal Commissioner of Taxation [2010] HCATrans 155 (16 June 2010) 3923–5 (D M J Bennett QC).
[177] Transcript of Proceedings, Aid/Watch Inc v Federal Commissioner of Taxation [2010] HCATrans 154 (15 June 2010) 1900–1 (D L Williams SC).
[178] Ibid 3086–92.
[179] Ibid 2968–3005, 3221–70 (D M J Bennett QC), citing especially Regan v Taxation with Representation of Washington[1983] USSC 91; , 461 US 540 (1983), Alliance for Life v Minister of National Revenue [1999] 3 FC 504 and Human Life International in Canada Inc v Minister of National Revenue [1998] 3 FC 202.
[180] Transcript of Proceedings, Aid/Watch Inc v Federal Commissioner of Taxation [2010] HCATrans 154 (15 June 2010) 3032–3 (D M J Bennett QC).
[181] Ibid 3035–40.
[182] Ibid 3072–4.
[183] Ibid 3076–9.
[184] Transcript of Proceedings, Aid/Watch Inc v Federal Commissioner of Taxation [2010] HCATrans 155 (16 June 2010) 3682–3 (D M J Bennett QC).
[185] Ibid 3690–3.
[186] Transcript of Proceedings, Aid/Watch Inc v Federal Commissioner of Taxation [2010] HCATrans 154 (15 June 2010) 1141–4.
[187] Ibid 1219–386 (French CJ, Gummow, Heydon and Kiefel JJ and D L Williams SC).
[188] Ibid 290–4.
[189] Gummow J initially suggested that the meaning of the legislative term should be governed by the meaning understood by the legislators of the time, and not expanded by subsequent common law decisions: ibid 306–12. In fact, the phrase ‘charitable institution’ appeared in the Income Tax Assessment Act 1915 (Cth) s 11, two years before the political purposes doctrine was developed in Bowman [1917] AC 406.
[190] Aid/Watch [2010] HCA 42; (2010) 241 CLR 539, 549 [23] (French CJ, Gummow, Hayne, Crennan and Bell JJ).
[191] Ibid.
[192] Ibid 557 [47] (French CJ, Gummow, Hayne, Crennan and Bell JJ).
[193] Ibid 557 [48].
[194] Ibid.
[195] Ibid 557 [47]–[49].
[196] Ibid 555 [42].
[197] Royal North Shore [1938] HCA 39; (1938) 60 CLR 396, 426.
[198] Aid/Watch [2010] HCA 42; (2010) 241 CLR 539, 556 [44] (French CJ, Gummow, Hayne, Crennan and Bell JJ).
[199] Ibid 556 [45].
[200] Ibid 550–4 [27]–[38].
[201] Ibid 561–2 [58].
[202] Ibid 563 [61].
[203] Ibid 563 [62].
[204] Ibid 564 [63].
[205] Ibid 565 [69].
[206] Ibid 567 [80].
[207] Ibid 567–8 [82].
[208] Ibid 568 [84].
[209] Ibid 568 [85].
[210] Ibid 564 [68].
[211] Ibid 566 [73].
[212] Ibid 565 [71].
[213] See, eg, Amnesty International Australia, Aid/Watch High Court Decision (27 January 2011) <http://www.amnesty.org.au/about/comments/24633> .
[214] The first empirical study has recently been conducted as to this effect in Australia: Esther Abram, ‘Freedom to Speak, Capacity to Act: Charity Law Reform Project — Removing the Barriers to Advocacy’ (Report, Changemakers Australia, March 2011).
[215] See generally Eric Barendt, Freedom of Speech (Oxford University Press, 2nd ed, 2005).
[216] Lange v Australian Broadcasting Corporation [1997] HCA 25; (1997) 189 CLR 520, 557–8 (Brennan CJ, Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron, McHugh, Gummow and Kirby JJ) (‘Lange’).
[217] Ibid 559.
[218] Peter Jones, ‘Freedom of Speech’ in Edward Craig (ed), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Routledge, 1998) vol 3, 762, 763. This definition is narrower than that employed by Meagher in his analysis of the underlying rationale: Dan Meagher, ‘What Is “Political Communication”? The Rationale and Scope of the Implied Freedom of Political Communication’ [2004] MelbULawRw 14; (2004) 28 Melbourne University Law Review 438. For a discussion of the other rationales for freedom of speech, see generally Barendt, above n 215, ch I.
[219] Lange [1997] HCA 25; (1997) 189 CLR 520, 560 (Brennan CJ, Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron, McHugh, Gummow and Kirby JJ).
[220] Ibid 561, 571–2. See also Hogan v Hinch [2011] HCA 4; (2011) 243 CLR 506, 543 [48] (French CJ); Coleman v Power [2004] HCA 39; (2004) 220 CLR 1, 45 [80], 49 [90] (McHugh J). The majority in Hogan v Hinch declined to discuss the submission in relation to the scope of the implied political freedom outside of the federal context: [2011] HCA 4; (2011) 243 CLR 506, 556 [99] (Gummow, Hayne, Heydon, Crennan, Kiefel and Bell JJ). Communications concerning the exercise of judicial power, however, are not ordinarily within the Lange freedom, except to the extent that they concern the acts or omissions of the legislature or government: APLA Ltd v Legal Services Commissioner (NSW) [2005] HCA 44; (2005) 224 CLR 322, 361 [65]–[66] (McHugh J). This was reaffirmed recently in Hogan v Hinch [2011] HCA 4; (2011) 243 CLR 506, 554–5 [92]–[93] (Gummow, Hayne, Heydon, Crennan, Kiefel and Bell JJ).
[221] See generally Barendt, above n 215, ch V.
[222] Lange [1997] HCA 25; (1997) 189 CLR 520, 560 (Brennan CJ, Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron, McHugh, Gummow and Kirby JJ).
[223] Ibid
561–2, reformulated in Coleman v Power [2004] HCA 39; (2004) 220 CLR
1, 50 [93] (McHugh J),
77–8 [196] (Gummow and Hayne JJ), 82 [211]
(Kirby J). See also Hogan v Hinch [2011] HCA 4; (2011) 243 CLR 506.
[224] Lange [1997] HCA 25; (1997) 189 CLR 520, 568 (Brennan CJ, Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron, McHugh, Gummow and Kirby JJ).
[225] Australian Capital Television Pty Ltd v Commonwealth [1992] HCA 45; (1992) 177 CLR 106, 169 (Deane and Toohey JJ). This was also emphasised in Mulholland v Australian Electoral Commission [2004] HCA 41; (2004) 220 CLR 181, 200 (Gleeson CJ) and Hogan v Hinch [2011] HCA 4; (2011) 243 CLR 506, 555–6 [95] (Gummow, Hayne, Heydon, Crennan, Kiefel and Bell JJ).
[226] Transcript of Proceedings, Aid/Watch Inc v Federal Commissioner of Taxation [2010] HCATrans 154 (15 June 2010) 3086–92.
[227] Aid/Watch [2010] HCA 42; (2010) 241 CLR 539, 556 [44] (French CJ, Gummow, Hayne, Crennan and Bell JJ).
[228] See Lange [1997] HCA 25; (1997) 189 CLR 520, 568–71 (Brennan CJ, Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron, McHugh, Gummow and Kirby JJ).
[229] Társaság a Szabadságjogokért v Hungary (2011) 53 EHRR 130, 136 [27] (citations omitted).
[230] See, eg, Re Draco Foundation (NZ) Charitable Trust (Unreported, High Court of New Zealand, Ronald Young J, 15 February 2011), especially at [60].
[231] (Unreported, High Court of New Zealand, Heath J, 6 May 2011) [59]. Heath J also referred to the use of mixed member proportional voting systems and the use of select committees to enable policy to be properly debated as other key features of the New Zealand system.
[232] Ibid, agreeing with Re Draco Foundation (NZ) Charitable Trust (Unreported, High Court of New Zealand, Ronald Young J, 15 February 2011) that the Court was bound by Molloy v Commissioner of Inland Revenue [1981] 1 NZLR 688 (Court of Appeal).
[233] Greenpeace New Zealand, Greenpeace Will Appeal High Court Decision on Charitable Status (10 May 2011) <http://www.greenpeace.org/new-zealand/en/news/Greenpeace-will-appeal-High-Court-decision-on-charitable-status> .
[234] [2004] HCA 39; (2004) 220 CLR 1, 78 [197] (Gummow and Hayne JJ). See also at 45–6 [81] (McHugh J), 91 [238]–[239] (Kirby J).
[235] Ibid 109 [291].
[236] Ibid 113–14 [299].
[237] Ibid 126 [332].
[238] Elisa Arcioni, ‘Developments in Free Speech Law in Australia: Coleman and Mulholland’ (2005) 33 Federal Law Review 333, 352.
[239] Aid/Watch [2010] HCA 42; (2010) 241 CLR 539, 561 [58].
[240] Coleman v Power [2004] HCA 39; (2004) 220 CLR 1, 113–14 [299].
[241] See Arcioni, above n 238, 340.
[242] [2010] HCA 42; (2010) 241 CLR 539, 556 [45] (French CJ, Gummow, Hayne, Crennan and Bell JJ).
[243] This phrase comes from Arcioni, above n 238, 340.
[244] The solicitors for Aid/Watch were part of the Social Justice Practice at Maurice Blackburn, which specialises in public interest litigation.
[245] See generally W K Jordan, Philanthropy in England 1480–1660: A Study of the Changing Pattern of English Social Aspirations (George Allen & Unwin, 1959); Jones, History of the Law of Charity, above n 16; Chesterman, above n 71; Jeremy Kendall and Martin Knapp, The Voluntary Sector in the United Kingdom (Manchester University Press, 1996); Mark Lyons, Third Sector: The Contribution of Nonprofit and Cooperative Enterprise in Australia (Allen & Unwin, 2001).
[246] See, eg, James Goodman, ‘Inside the Aid/Watch Case: Translating Across Political and Legal Activism’ (2011) 3(3s) Cosmopolitan Civil Societies: An Interdisciplinary Journal 46, 60, which discusses the high financial stakes for Aid/Watch in its application for leave to appeal to the High Court.
[247] Aid/Watch [2010] HCA 42; (2010) 241 CLR 539, 557 [47] (French CJ, Gummow, Hayne, Crennan and Bell JJ).
[248] Ibid 562–4 [60]–[62].
[249] Ibid 567–8 [80]–[86].
[250] Ibid 557 [49] (French CJ, Gummow, Hayne, Crennan and Bell JJ).
[251] See Matthew Harding, ‘Distinguishing Government from Charity in Australian Law’ [2009] SydLawRw 23; (2009) 31 Sydney Law Review 559.
[252] Aid/Watch [2010] HCA 42; (2010) 241 CLR 539, 555–6 [44] (French CJ, Gummow, Hayne, Crennan and Bell JJ).
[253] Ibid 557 [48].
[254] Transcript of Proceedings, Aid/Watch Inc v Federal Commissioner of Taxation [2010] HCATrans 154 (15 June 2010) 1219–20 (Gummow J), 1386 (French CJ).
[255] [2006] HCA 43; (2006) 228 CLR 168. This case considered the relationship between charity and government.
[256] [2008] HCA 55; (2008) 236 CLR 204. This case considered the relationship between charity and business activity.
[257] Parachin, above n 72, 899.
[258] Aid/Watch Inc v Federal Commissioner of Taxation [2008] AATA 652 (28 July 2008) [21].
[259] Sheppard Report, above n 12, 123–5. See also Rob Atkinson, ‘Altruism in Nonprofit Organizations’ (1990) 31 Boston College Law Review 501; OLRC, above n 18, 149; John F Coverdale, ‘The Normative Justification for Tax Exemption: Elements from Catholic Social Thought’ (2010) 40 Seton Hall Law Review 889, 898–9.
[260] See, eg, Rob Atkinson, ‘Theories of the Federal Income Tax Exemption for Charities: Thesis, Antithesis and Synthesis’ in Paul Bater, Frits Hondius and Penina Kessler Lieber (eds), The Tax Treatment of NGOs: Legal, Fiscal and Ethical Standards for Promoting NGOs and Their Activities (Kluwer Law International, 2004) 253, 259; David E Pozen, ‘Remapping the Charitable Deduction’ (2006) 39 Connecticut Law Review 531, 564–5.
[261] Chesterman, above n 71, 52.
[262] See, eg, John D Colombo, ‘The Role of Tax Exemption in a Competitive Health Care Market’ (2006) 31 Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law 623.
[263] Steve
Coll, ‘Nonprofit Newspapers’, The New Yorker
(online), 28 January 2009
<http://www.newyorker.com/online/blogs/stevecoll/2009/01/nonprofit-newsp.html>
Thomas Ferraro, ‘US Bill Seeks to Rescue Faltering Newspapers’,
Reuters (online), 24 March 2009
<http://www.reuters.com/article/2009/03/24/us-usa-congress-newspapers-idUSTRE52N67F2009
0324>.
[264] For an overview, see Richard Steinberg, ‘Economic Theories of Nonprofit Organisations’ in Walter W Powell and Richard Steinberg (eds), The Nonprofit Sector: A Research Handbook (Yale University Press, 2nd ed, 2006) 117.
[265] An analogy can be made with Federal Commissioner of Taxation v Wentworth District Capital Ltd [2011] FCAFC 42; (2011) 191 FCR 151. This case concerned a tax exemption for a non-profit banking service in a rural town, which qualified as an ‘association established for community service purposes’ under the Income Tax Assessment Act 1997 (Cth), rather than under the charitable tax exemption.
[266] This is most famously articulated in the ‘three failures’ theory: see generally Burton A Weisbrod, ‘Toward a Theory of the Voluntary Non-Profit Sector in a Three-Sector Economy’ in Edmund S Phelps (ed), Altruism, Morality, and Economic Theory (Russell Sage Foundation, 1975) 171; Burton A Weisbrod, The Voluntary Nonprofit Sector: An Economic Analysis (Lexington Books, 1977); Henry B Hansmann, ‘The Role of Nonprofit Enterprise’ (1980) 89 Yale Law Journal 835; Lester M Salamon, ‘Of Market Failure, Voluntary Failure, and Third-Party Government: Toward a Theory of Government–Nonprofit Relations in the Modern Welfare State’ (1987) 16(1–2) Nonprofit and Voluntary Sector Quarterly 29.
[267] For alternative perspectives on the economic nature of community goods, see Roger A Lohmann, ‘And Lettuce Is Nonanimal: Toward a Positive Economics of Voluntary Action’ (1989) 18 Nonprofit and Voluntary Sector Quarterly 367; Johnny Rex Buckles, ‘The Community Income Theory of the Charitable Contributions Deduction’ (2005) 80 Indiana Law Journal 947.
[268] A ‘multiple pathways’ model is similarly suggested in Lateral Economics, ‘The Case for Retaining the FBT Concession for Not for Profit Hospitals/Aged Care and Public Benevolent Institutions (Charities)’ (Report, April 2010) 42–3.
[269] United Kingdom, Royal Commission on the Income Tax, Report, Cmd 615 (1920) 68 [307] (‘Colwyn Committee Report’); United Kingdom, Royal Commission on the Taxation of Profits and Income, Final Report, Cmd 9474 (1955) 56–7 [170]–[172] (‘Radcliffe Report’).
[270] Goodman Report, above n 89, 143–4 (minority report); Trevor C W Farrow, ‘The Limits of Charity: Redefining the Boundaries of Charitable Trust Law’ (1994) 13 Estates and Trusts Journal 306; Michael Gousmett, ‘A Legislative Definition of “Charitable Purpose”’ [2003] New Zealand Law Journal 78.
[271] Jordan, above n 245, 281.
[273] Ibid 145–6.
[274] Ibid 147–8. Finnis’s ultimate goods include: life, knowledge, play, aesthetic experience, friendship, religion, and practical reasonableness (the basic good of being able to bring one’s own intelligence to bear effectively on one’s life).
[275] Ibid 149.
[277] [2008] FCA 983; (2008) 170 FCR 318.
[279] Dal Pont, Law of Charity, above n 3, 281–2 [12.2]–[12.3].
[281] Dal Pont, Law of Charity, above n 3, 48–59 [3.3]–[3.19].
[283] Ibid ch 4.
[284] Aid/Watch, About Aid/Watch, above n 123.
[285] Pete Alcock, ‘Building the Big Society: A New Policy Environment for the Third Sector in England’ (2010) 1 Voluntary Sector Review 379.
[286] There will, of course, always be disputes about which norms are ‘core’ political norms, and the application of such norms to a particular context. To some extent, this can be addressed in a legal context by assessing the strength of particular legal norms. This is done in various contexts such as interpreting statutes in light of principles of human rights, or assessing whether a norm has become a norm of customary international law. For example, see the discussion by Lord Steyn of ‘the legal right of equality with the correlative right of non-discrimination on the grounds of race’ in R (European Roma Rights Centre) v Immigration Officer at Prague Airport [2004] UKHL 55; [2005] 2 AC 1, 46 [46].
[287] See, eg, Stephanie Palmer, ‘Public Functions and Private Services: A Gap in Human Rights Protection’ (2008) 6 International Journal of Constitutional Law 585; Colin D Campbell, ‘The Nature of Power as Public in English Judicial Review’ (2009) 68 Cambridge Law Journal 90.
[288] International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, opened for signature 16 December 1966, 999 UNTS 171 (entered into force 23 March 1976) art 20(2).
[289] Aileen Kavanagh, ‘Deference or Defiance? The Limits of the Judicial Role in Constitutional Adjudication’ in Grant Huscroft (ed), Expounding the Constitution: Essays in Constitutional Theory (Cambridge University Press, 2008) 184.
[290] Jeff A King, ‘Institutional Approaches to Judicial Restraint’ (2008) 28 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 409, 435.
[291] Public Trustee (1997) 42 NSWLR 600, 620.
[292] Commonwealth
of Australia, ‘Not-for-Profit (NFP) Sector Reforms’ (Fact Sheet, 28
July 2011)
<http://www.futuretax.gov.au/content/Content.aspx?doc=FactSheets/reform_for_nfp_sector.htm>
The Treasury (Cth), Not-for-Profit Reform
<http://treasury.gov.au/content/not_for_profit.
asp?ContentID=2188&titl=Not-for-profit%20Reform>;
Commonwealth of Australia, Australian Charities and
Not-for-Profits Commission Implementation Taskforce
<http://acnctaskforce.
treasury.gov.au>.
[293] Commonwealth of Australia, ‘A Definition of Charity’ (Consultation Paper, October 2011) <http://www.treasury.gov.au/documents/2161/PDF/definition_v6.pdf> .
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/UMelbLRS/2011/9.html