Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
University of New South Wales Faculty of Law Research Series |
Last Updated: 5 September 2008
INTERROGATING TERRORIST SUSPECTS: CRIMINAL JUSTICE AND CONTROL PROCESS IN THREE AUSTRALIAN CASES
David Dixon[*]
Abstract
This paper examines three cases in which people suspected of terrorist activity were questioned by Australian police and security officers. They are located in the context of fundamental shifts in criminal justice processes and principles. Debates about interrogating terrorist suspects are dominated by concerns about torture. It is argued here that such concerns need to be supplemented by paying more attention to everyday questioning in the increasing mass of ‘ordinary’ terrorist cases.
INTRODUCTION
The questioning of suspects
takes place within a broader context of institutional practices, priorities and
values. This paper will
indicate that this context is undergoing fundamental
change in most Western democracies. What had been generally accepted as
fundamental
principles of criminal justice are being compromised, devalued and
even abandoned in a shift towards what is better understood as
a control process
with very different values and priorities. These general trends will be
illustrated by reference to examples of
how some people thought to be connected
to terrorist activities have been interviewed by Australian authorities, and the
judicial
consideration of the products of such questioning. The roles of
prosecutors and of government will also be considered.
Exponents of
investigative interviewing need to be aware of these contextual changes. It will
be argued that the current focus on
interrogation of major suspects needs to be
widened to take account of and make provision for the more common questioning of
those
on the margins.
FROM CRIMINAL JUSTICE...
In the twentieth century, a
paradigm of criminal justice matured in Anglophone jurisdictions in which
questioning of suspects had
a specific place (Dixon, 2008). Suspects should be
interviewed in a closely regulated period between being arrested and being
charged
with an offence. Such questioning should normally take place at a police
station where police supervisors were responsible for ensuring
access to various
rights, notably of access to legal advice. The length of investigative detention
was restricted by time limits
(eg in England and Wales under the Police and
Criminal Evidence Act 1984, a maximum of 96 hours, although regulatory hurdles
ensured
that most suspects were charged or released within six hours.) After
being charged, a suspect could not be interviewed about that
offence. These were
specific expressions of a criminal justice paradigm with deep roots in liberal
democratic conceptions of relations
between state and citizen.
For those
of us who professionally grew up seeing these arrangements as normal, it is
important to appreciate their relatively recent
origins. Until the
mid-nineteenth century, magistrates, not police, directed criminal
investigations. Until the mid-twentieth century,
the propriety of police
questioning suspects between arrest and charge was unclear. For a long period,
such questioning attracted
judicial criticism. Until legislative interventions
in many jurisdictions in the late twentieth century, the legality of
investigative
detention was contested (Dixon, 1997).
This confined and
contested conception of interviewing’s place was both product and part of
a broader criminal justice paradigm.
Key characteristics of this approach
include:
... TO CONTROL PROCESS
In the last decade, a new paradigm has taken shape which I will call a ‘control process’, emphasising that its concerns are neither exclusively about what is ‘criminal’ nor ‘justice’ in the senses commonly understood in the paradigm of criminal justice. The key characteristics of this paradigm are in stark contrast to those of criminal justice:
The central concepts of liberal democratic criminal justice are
devalued in the new control process. The key concern is now the minimization
of
risk and the security of the group. The individual is no longer the centre of
attention, and so there is less emphasis on the
individual’s rights and
the need to prove the individual’s guilt beyond reasonable doubt through a
system of due process.
Flexibility of process replaces certainty of rules and
procedures as a virtue. ‘Pre-emption’, compliance and efficiency
are
more important than individual punishment or due process: preventive detention
for potential sex-offenders and others, anti-social
behaviour orders, behaviour
management contracts, non-association and space restriction order, and the use
of bail conditions as
a proactive crime control measure are just the more
prominent examples. There is less interest in understanding crime’s
causation
than in accepting crime as normal, a choice to be controlled and
insured against, in which “attempts to cure or punish appear
less logical
than do moves to manage crime and minimize its costs” (Zedner, 2005a:
284). The state’s responsibility for
crime control is “contracted
out to private providers wielding state franchises, delegated to individuals and
communities,
or completely over taken by the growing private security
industry” (Zedner, 2005a: 284). Policing intervenes proactively,
preventing
and pre-empting problems rather than retrospectively solving them.
Simply to say that all this goes against basic principle is rather like
complaining that a game of chess isn’t being played
according to the rules
of draughts. The game has changed, allowing those in government to dismiss the
standard civil libertarian
response to new police powers as anachronistic and
irrelevant. The contrast between criminal justice and control process is
exaggerated
here in order to clarify the difference. It has become trite to
respond to by pointing out that criminal justice has always included
substantial
preventive elements. The modern English policing tradition has a strong
preventive commitment in the Peelite tradition.
Preventive detention has been
possible for those refused bail, the mentally ill, habitual offenders, those
suffering from certain
infectious diseases, illegal migrants, refugees, sex
offenders and others. Similarly, deterrence is by nature forward-looking: but
its activation depends on a crime having been committed. This illustrates the
essential point that while criminal justice includes
preventive and deterrent
elements, these do not change the ideological core commitment to a reactive,
individualistic process.
While these developments have been underway for
some time, they accelerated quickly after 9/11. Parliaments are now in a
constant
cycle of extending anti-terrorism legislation in ways that routinely
deviate from liberal democratic principles in the name of necessity.
It must be
acknowledged that the shift from criminal justice to control process did not
happen suddenly on 9/11 any more than Islamic
terrorism arrived on the world
stage on that day. Rather, the response to terrorism must be seen as hastening
changes which were
already under way, notably in the other ‘war’ of
our times, that on illegal drugs. The law enforcement response to illegal
drugs
(and the organized crime associated with their distribution) has entailed a long
series of compromises and exceptions to basic
principle, reducing and shifting
the burden of proof reduced from prosecution to defence and deploying
incapacitative civil and criminal
penalties. The contrast between criminal
justice and control process is exaggerated here in order to clarify the
difference. It
has become trite to respond to by pointing out that criminal
justice has always included substantial preventive elements. The modern
English
policing tradition has a strong preventive commitment in the Peelite tradition.
Preventive detention has been possible for
those refused bail, the mentally ill,
habitual offenders, those suffering from certain infectious diseases, illegal
migrants, refugees,
sex offenders and others. Similarly, deterrence is by
nature forward-looking: but its activation depends on a crime having been
committed. This illustrates the essential point that while criminal justice
includes preventive and deterrent elements, these do
not change the ideological
core commitment to a reactive, individualistic process. In addition, much of the
groundwork for the new
paradigm’s emphasis on preventative intervention
and detention was laid in responses to perceived threats from sexual predators
and other dangerous risks.
However, the fundamental difference between
criminal justice and control process is real and marked, and there is a shift
from the
former to the latter. These differences can be illustrated through
analysis of the different role of interrogation in the two paradigms.
In the
criminal justice paradigm, police question a suspect between arrest and charge
in order to obtain evidence which may be admissible
subsequently in court about
specific offences allegedly committed by the suspect. In the control process
paradigm, the purpose of
interrogation may be much broader: the focus is not the
suspect’s past actions but what he or she knows about future actions
by
others. In response to 9/11, “the interest of investigators has shifted
from obtaining viable evidence for prosecution to
obtaining credible information
for preventing future acts of terrorism” (Strauss, 2003: 206). In this
context, what counts
as success may be much less than obtaining a confession:
Interrogators find tiny bits of the truth, fragments of information, slivers of data. We enter a vast desert, hundreds of miles across, in which a few thousand puzzle pieces have been scattered. We spend weeks on a single prisoner, to extract only a single piece – if that. We collect, and then we pass the pieces on, hoping that someone above us can assemble them (Mackey, 2004: xxv).
Controls on interrogation which are designed around the potential sanction of evidence being excluded as inadmissible are of limited value when producing admissible evidence is not the main objective. Criminal justice and control process are paradigms. They are neither clearly distinct nor sequential, with one simply replacing the other. Rather it is exactly the discordant overlap which will emerge as a significant problem in some of the specific cases to be discussed below.
TORTURE AND INTERROGATION
Perhaps to the disappointment of some and the relief
of others, this chapter is not primarily concerned with torture. While only a
few years ago, torture was widely (although wrongly) regarded as a historical
relic, its modern use has spawned a vast literature.
The disclosure of (some of)
what happened in Abu Ghraib and the global prison network of the USA’s
affiliates has been an extraordinary
achievement by investigative journalists
and human rights organizations. It provided the spur for many in the West to
question and
challenge the post 9/11 policies and actions of the USA and its
allies. However, this concentration of attention appears problematic
from two
perspectives. First, some academic discussion of torture seems to share some
elements of the dark, obsessional, almost pornogaphic,
interest displayed in
some contemporary films and TV series. Secondly, and more relevant to this
chapter’s concerns, the focus
on the negative means that we have been
concerned with what must not be done rather than what can and should be done in
questioning
suspects. My particular interest is in what should be permissible in
the routine, everyday questioning of those thought to be on
the edges (or
connected to the edges) of activities under investigation. For every
high-profile suspect, there are hundreds of people
who the authorities detain
and question in the process of accumulating the vast banks of information on
which counter-terrorism depends.
The issue of torture – its morality,
legality and effectiveness – has dominated debates about interrogation
related to
terrorism. This has been inevitable: the fact that at the time of
writing, there continues to be serious talk about whether simulated
drowning
should be regarded as torture is an indication of how far the compass has
shifted in recent
years.[2] While it may
have been necessary, the debate on torture and what should not be done in
interrogation dragged attention away from the practical question of what
should be done. The answer to this question depends in part on the moral
dilemmas founding the torture debate. But it also depends on what
the
interrogation is for. If the interrogation is part of a process which
will or may lead to criminal law prosecution, the answer will be very different
than if the interrogation is part of an intelligence-gathering exercise. Of
course, in reality this distinction is very difficult
to maintain. As we will
see in the discussion below of Australian cases, the overlap between criminal
justice and control process
has proved to be very problematic
A good example
of the problems is provided by a contribution to a conference on ‘Law and
liberty in the war on terror’
by Neil James, who has operational,
supervisory and training experience in interrogation. His paper provides a
familiar critique
of torture, focusing on instrumental issues of effectiveness
and practicality. He seeks to distinguish torture from legitimate interrogation.
Quoting from the Australian Defence Force’s Interrogators’
Handbook, (of which he was the original author), James states:
Among professional interrogators in countries abiding by the rule of law the common working definition of interrogation is ‘the systematic extraction of information from an individual, either willing or unwilling, by the use of psychological attack only’. Thus, interrogation is essentially an intellectual process not a physical one. No physical or mental pain or severe suffering is involved. The subject is convinced to cooperate by reasoning and by overcoming their will to resist (2007: 161).
Some may argue that the line between torture and interrogation is not so
defined as James suggest. However, this is not my concern
here. Rather, my focus
is on the acceptability of this form of interrogation in a criminal justice
model. Any evidence lawyer’s
ears would have pricked up at this account of
interrogation: unwilling extraction of information, psychological attack, and
overcoming
of the will to resist provide ready ammunition for an argument that a
confession was involuntary, so failing to get past the first
requirement of
evidential admissibility.
The problem is clarified when James goes further,
justifying “measures or conditions of discomfort or annoyance designed to
encourage cooperation are not unreasonable ... With obvious safeguards such
conditioning may, for example, legally include the strictly
controlled and
temporary use of measures such as isolation, sensory deprivation or sleep
deprivation” (2007: 162). While it
may be the case that such treatment
does not amount to criminal offences, it certainly would render any confession
thereby produced
inadmissible under the current law of evidence in many
countries.
James is concerned with more serious and difficult cases. My
primary interest is rather different. An interrogation to discover a
‘ticking bomb’ will happen very rarely, if ever, despite the
enormous attention this ‘scenario’ has attracted.
Stepping down the
scale of seriousness, few interrogators will be called on to deal with the kind
of suspect for whom even techniques
such as sleep deprivation could be
considered as appropriate. Just as has often been the case in policing more
generally, there is
an unfortunate concentration on everything except the
everyday and ‘normal’ practice. The vast majority of terrorism
related interrogations will continue to involve low-level people on the fringes.
For them, length of detention will be the critical
variable.
A now standard
part of critiques of torture and related techniques is that other methods are
more effective, even in questioning those
allegedly involved in terrorism. In
particular, it is argued that interviewers with appropriate language skills,
cultural knowledge
and training can build rapport with suspects and thereby
produce results (Gelles et al., 2006; Pearse, 2006). The problem is that
such
rapport is most unlikely to be established in the short periods allowed under
standard criminal justice regimes. As Gelles
et al. suggest, “A
rapport-building (or relationship-based) approach will yield the best results in
an interview/interrogation
that occurs over days/weeks/months” (2006: 31).
James confirms that “the time available” is crucial (2007: 161).
In
these approaches, it is taken for granted that the subject of interrogation must
be detained for an extended period in order for
interrogation to be successful.
Yet this runs counter to one of the basic principles of criminal justice regimes
such as PACE which
were constructed on an understanding that extended detention
in itself could make confessions unreliable because people would say
anything
(even at long term cost) to win a short term reprieve from investigative
detention.
If interrogation is intended to produce confessions and
admissions which are acceptable to a criminal justice paradigm, lengthy
pre-charge
detention is unacceptable because it undermines the voluntariness
which is a precondition of evidential admissibility. If interrogation
is
primarily intended to produce information and actionable intelligence rather
than admissible evidence, then the concerns of criminal
justice will not be
paramount. In addition, problems for the authorities arise when the lengthy
interrogation for intelligence is
over. Are the subjects of interrogation to be
detained for ever (or until the ‘war on terror’ is over, if there is
a
difference)? Are they simply to be released and placed under administrative
control orders which limit their movements and contacts?
Or should an attempt be
made to create an ersatz criminal justice, dressing up a militaristic control
process with some trappings
of legality? These are, of course, the questions
which the USA has been grappling with over the detainees at Guantanamo Bay.
INTERROGATING TERRORISM: THREE CASE-STUDIES
Much of the extensive post 9/11 literature on ‘liberty versus security’ and related changes in criminal justice has been general and abstract. This section seeks to provide a closer focus through brief analysis of three Australian cases involving alleged terrorist offences in which controversial interrogations have played crucial roles.
i. Jack Thomas
In 2003, Jack Thomas (an Australian citizen) was
arrested and detained for five months in Pakistan. During this period, he was
‘interrogated
numerous times by Pakistani, American and Australian
officials, often whilst blindfolded, hooded and shackled’ (Lynch, 2006:
313). According to his account, which was accepted as truthful by an Australian
court, he was assaulted, threatened with torture
and with the rape of his wife,
and offered inducements of favourable treatment in return for cooperation.
In a final session in Pakistan, Thomas was interviewed by Australian Federal
Police (AFP) agents. This took place in the same room
as previous interviews
with security and police officials, and the AFP interviewers had both attended
some of the previous sessions.
The purpose of this interview was ‘to
gather evidence in a form and by a process that would be admissible in an
Australian
court’ (Lynch, 2006: 314). It was, in other words, an attempt
to bridge the gap between control process and criminal justice,
between a series
of interviews conducted in a security facility in a foreign country and the
proceedings of an Australian court.
In this interview, the AFP agents
attempted to meet criminal process requirements, explaining the right to silence
and emphasising
that participation in the interview was voluntary. The relevant
Australian law requires a suspect to be provided with access to legal
advice:
the AFP tried to arrange this, but Pakistani Inter-Service Intelligence
officials refused (Lynch, 2006: 315). The Victorian
Court of Appeal commented
that the interview was ‘conducted in what can be reasonably described as a
conventional fashion’
(R v Thomas [2006] VSCA 165 at para 51). Statements
made by Thomas in this interview were subsequently presented as part of the case
against him when (more than
year later) he was arrested and charged in Australia
with offences of receiving funds from and providing support to a terrorist
organisation.
The crucial issue for the Australian courts was whether the
final interview could be distinguished from what had preceded it so that
the
evidence produced could meet criminal justice standards – notably, the
base requirement that a confession or admission
must be made voluntarily. In a
voir dire, the trial judge ruled that the admissions had been made voluntarily:
Thomas was convicted
and sentenced to five years’ imprisonment. Narrow
legalism, sympathy to police and prosecutors, and a narrow view of reality
have
often been characteristics of Australian criminal trial judges. The trial judge
concluded that Thomas had a choice to answer
questions or not, and exercised
that choice. The pressure to answer came not from the interviewers ‘either
expressly or implicitly’,
but from Thomas’s own assessment of the
‘risk of indefinite detention in Pakistan or of removal to the United
States
or Cuba’ (DPP v Thomas [2006] VSC 243 at para. 42). The judge found
that this interview could be distinguished from the earlier interviews and the
inducements offered
in them: “There was a clear bifurcation in purpose,
function and form between the ASIO interviews and the AFP interview. Mr
Thomas
fully understood it” (ibid. at para. 50).
The Victorian Court of
Appeal rejected this artificiality and restated the accepted common law
principle that an earlier inducement
(which may be a threat or promise –
in lawyers’ terminology, “fear of prejudice or hope of
advantage”) offered
by a person in authority (such as the security
interviewers) can continue to affect the suspect’s voluntariness. The
Court
of Appeal’s conclusion was the same as any commonsense understanding
of the situation – the final interview could not
be divorced from those
preceding it – “same place, same AFP personnel, same topics”
(2006 VSCA 165 at para 84).
Obviously, the fact and circumstances of his detention, the various inducements held out and threats made to him, the prospect that he would remain detained indefinitely, can be seen to have operated upon the mind of the applicant when he decided to participate in the (final AFP) interview. Whist nothing occurred in the interview itself that could be seen to overbear the will of the applicant, there can be little doubt that he was, at that time, subject to externally-imposed pressure of a kind calculated to overbear his will and thereby restrict, in a practical sense, his available choices and the manner of their exercise. (ibid, para 92)
The AFP’s attempt to lay
a patina of criminal justice over a structure of control process was rejected.
Notably, the failure
to provide access to legal advice could not be excused
simply because the refusal was by the local authorities, not the Australian
investigators. Their refusal meant that an interview conforming with Australian
law could not be conducted in Pakistan (ibid., para
111).
For the future in
a case like Thomas’s, the alternatives for the authorities are clear.
Either there must be a much greater
distinction in time, place and personnel
between interrogations carried out for different purposes, or prosecutions must
be based
on evidence other than confessions or admissions, or an alternative to
criminal justice must be deployed. As will be shown below,
the Australian
authorities are exploring all options. From this perspective, the trial
judge’s convolutions in Thomas’s
case are understandable: however
flawed, they represented an attempt to maintain the relevance of a criminal
justice paradigm.
ii. Mohammed Haneef
Dr Mohammed Haneef, an Indian doctor practising in
Queensland, was detained following the London and Glasgow car-bomb incidents in
June 2007. These marked a significant shift in concern about terrorism. The
previously accepted wisdom was that the threat of terrorism
was associated with
alienation and anomie in ethnic minorities: yet those allegedly associated with
the London and Glasgow incidents
were not unemployed inner-city youth, but
doctors. The shift from risk to precaution (Zedner, 2005b; 2007a) is
illustrated by this.
If members of a professional elite were engaged in
terrorism, the attempt to identify auditable risk factors seems doomed: instead,
the authorities respond as if risk is all around and that precautionary action
is necessary.
Dr Haneef’s alleged connection to the British incidents
was that he was second cousin to a man who died from burns suffered
in the
Glasgow incident and a telephone SIM card purchased by Haneef had been found
with the alleged bombers’ possessions.
Suspicion was increased by his
attempt to board a flight from Australia to India. With at least tacit
encouragement from a government
facing a general election which had previously
exploited security scares for political advantage, sections of the media treated
Haneef
as a prize capture. It was alleged, for example, that he was planning to
blow up an apartment block on Queensland’s Gold Coast,
a tourist area.
The ‘case’ against Haneef then spectacularly fell apart: his
flight to India was to see his newborn child; the apartment
bomb story was based
on no more than a photograph of Haneef and his wife on a Gold Coast beach; the
SIM card was found not, as initially
reported, in the vehicle driven into
Glasgow airport, but in Liverpool. (Haneef had passed it on when he left England
so that the
remaining credit would not be wasted.) As in Thomas’s case, we
see the courts applying the criminal justice principles; but
these rub hard
against exigencies of the new control process. When a magistrate took the brave
and unusual step of ordering Haneef’s
release on bail, the Australian
Government intervened by withdrawing his immigration visa and converting
investigative detention
into pre-deportation detention. The ‘orthodox
process’ of law was overtaken by administrative discretion (Lynch, 2007:
228). This was done in a way (citing the national interest) which sought
(ultimately unsuccessfully) to prevent judicial scrutiny
of the decision.
Exposure of the weakness of the prosecution case and widespread public criticism
of the police followed. While the
Australian government continued to mutter
darkly about Haneef’s connections with terrorism, the Commonwealth
Director of Public
Prosecutions eventually dropped the charges against Haneef.
He was released, and left for India to see his daughter for the first
time
(Lynch, 2007: 226-7). In a final humiliation for the Government, the Federal
Court (in a decision which was scathing about the
Immigration Minister’s
behaviour) ruled that the visa cancellation was unlawful. At the time of
writing, Dr Haneef was considering
returning to resume his medial career in
Australia.
Interrogations conducted by Australia Federal Police agents
with Dr Haneef played a vital part in this reversal. Haneef was interviewed
over
several days. ‘He was the first person to be detained under new
anti-terrorism powers which enable Australian police to
hold a suspect without
charge for an extended period of time during which questioning up to a maximum
of 24 hours may occur’
(Lynch, 2007: 225). The interviews were lengthy but
were carried out in accordance with criminal justice values and standards. The
relevant legislation follows the standard practice of specifying a maximum
period for active investigation to which is added ‘time
outs’ in
which the detention clock is stopped while other investigations take place, and
the suspects is allowed to rest and
eat. The indeterminate length of detention
under a ‘time out’ system has been criticised. However, the problem
of lengthy
detention had rarely been so clearly demonstrated as in
Haneef’s case: he was detained for 12 days before being charged with
providing ‘support or resources’ to organisation involved in
terrorist activity (Lynch, 2007: 225-6). This was a much
longer period than
those responsible for drafting the legislation had thought would occur (Lynch,
2007: 228).
The interviewers were polite and respectful, if not very well
prepared. We know this because Dr Haneef’s barrister, Stephen
Keim,
responded to the Government, police and media misrepresentation of his client by
releasing the transcript of the first of the
recorded interviews to the
press.[3] Apart from
demonstrating Haneef’s apparently full cooperation, the transcripts
revealed that aspects of the prosecutions case
against Haneef were unfounded: he
had, for example, a good reason for his supposedly suspicious attempted
departure from Australia.
It emerged that some of his actions were apparently
inconsistent with guilt – for example, far from fleeing from
investigators,
he had made several attempts to contact the UK police (Lynch,
2007: 227). When the Immigration Minister proceeded to selectively
release
passages from the second interview in an attempt to justify his stance, while
claiming that he was unable to release the
full record on the basis that it
might prejudice ongoing police investigations (Lynch 2007: 227), Haneef’s
lawyers again released
the full transcript. Its anodyne contents deflated the
government’s attempts to justify Haneef’s treatment. As in other
contexts, a comprehensive record of interview (ie not just a recording of a
rehashed confession) can provide suspect as well as police
with valuable
resources (Dixon, 2007).
iii. Izhar Ul-Haque
In early 2003, Izhar Ul-Haque, an Australian citizen,
spent three weeks at a camp in Pakistan organised by Lashkar-e-Taiba, which
would subsequently be prescribed under Australian law as a terrorist
organization. Six months after his return to Australia, Ul-Haque
was
interrogated by Australian Security Intelligence Organisation (ASIO) officers
and subsequently was charged with an offence of
training with a terrorist
organisation. The circumstances of Ul-Haque’s interrogation emerged at his
trial. In his ruling on
a voir dire concerning the results of this
interrogation, the trial judge was scathing about ASIO’s conduct: not only
refusing
to admit the interview records into evidence, he concluded that the
investigating officers had committed significant criminal and
civil offences
in their treatment of Ul-Haque. His judgement provides a vivid picture of the
contrast between criminal justice and
control process.
As noted above, in
the criminal justice paradigm, interrogation is designed to produce information
and, if appropriate, admissible
evidence about an offence committed by an
individual. In Ul-Haque’s case, the function of the alleged offence was as
a lever
with which to put pressure on Ul-Haque to collect and provide
information about a person suspected of more serious offences: the
trial judge
commented “It seems almost certain that the action taken against the
accused by the authorities was instigated
by his being connected with one Fadeen
Lodhi”. (Lodhi was later convicted of terrorism offences.) Ul-Haque had a
family connection
with Lodhi: communication between the two following
Ul-Haque’s return from Pakistan was what “excited the authorities
and instigated the actions of the authorities that led to interviews here in
question and his ultimately being charged” (R
v Ul-Haque [2007] NSWSC 1251
at para 13). According to Ul-Haque, the officers told him that they did not wish
to speak to him about his training in Pakistan:
“They said, ‘No, we
know about that. We’re not concerned with that’” (ibid., para.
21). An officer
told the court that his colleagues questioned Ul-Haque because
“we had an investigation underway and we had information which
indicated
(he) had information which could assist us in that investigation” (ibid.,
para 30). Ul-Haque claimed that an officer
told him “we see you as a
helper, as an informant and as a witness ... I don’t think you have done
anything wrong”
(ibid., para. 78).
In November 2003, ASIO officers
intercepted Ul-Haque at a railway station on his way home from university, where
he was studying
medicine. He was not formally arrested. The officers’ and
Ul-Haque’s accounts of the initial confrontation differed somewhat,
but
the differences were not significant. It is clear that what occurred was a very
familiar example of an order lightly camouflaged
as a request: as Ul-Haque
commented, “the thought of choice never really occurred because I was
under extreme pressure and
stress” (ibid para 21. On the relationship of
‘consent’ to the exercise of police powers, see Dixon, 1997: ch.4.)
As the judge concluded, “Although it is described as a request, ... his
being told to accompany them to a nearby park was an
instruction and was
intended to be taken as such” (op. cit., para 27).
Sitting between two
officers in the back of a car, he was taken to a public park and questioned
about his knowledge of Lodhi. An ASIO
officer told him that “he was in
substantial trouble and that his full cooperation with ASIO ... would be
required” (ibid.,
para 25). On the officers’ own account, this
included “robust discussion and considerable prompting from the
interviewing
officers” (ibid., para 23). The interrogation was not
contemporaneously recorded, and again the two sides’ accounts differed
in
tone. They agreed that he was given a choice of cooperation or facing the
consequences of failing to do so: in the officers’
account, this meant
continued investigation, while in Ul-Haque’s it meant action against him
unless he collected and provided
information about Lodhi (ibid., paras 20-1). To
a young Muslim man aware of contemporary developments in the ‘war on
terror’,
the possible implications of the threat were very serious:
...when he said ... “we can do this the easy way or the hard way”, I believed that unless I kept ... answering their questions that they will use the hard way (which) to me meant ... for example that I could either be deported , I could be arrested, I could be taken to a secret location for interrogation ... and my family ... would be taken into custody (ibid., para 71)
The judge accepted Ul-Haque’s account of his fears:
“the accused was given to understand that it was in his interests
to
co-operate, and there was an implicit threat that if he did not do so some
adverse consequences might follow” (ibid., para
67).
Ul-Haque was then
interviewed further in the car on the way to his parents’ house, which was
being searched by some 25 ASIO
and police officers, and again on the way back to
the railway station where Ul-Haque’s car had been left. He then returned,
accompanied by an agent, to his parents’ house, where he was interviewed
for a further 2 hours and 46 minutes, ending at 3.45am.
Later that day, and then
again five days later, he was subjected to further questioning, on these
occasions at a police station by
Federal Police agents. Two weeks later (after
numerous telephone contacts), the agents returned to Ul-Haque’s house. The
AFP’s
account was that they requested Ul-Haque to “further assist
the Federal Police by undertaking covert enquiries or acting as
a
witness”. Ul-Haque’s account was that they threatened to prevent him
from continuing to study medicine and “make
life difficult” for his
family (ibid., para 110)
Many people will not be surprised at how ASIO
treated Ul-Haque: this is how an intelligence agency may be expected to behave.
The
problem arose when an attempt was made to shift from control process to
criminal justice by charging him. (The real motivation appears
to have been to
punish him for non-cooperation with ASIO rather than for his brief involvement
with Lashkar-e-Taiba.) What might
have been conventional security agency
practice came under intense, critical scrutiny in a criminal court. The judge
was merciless
in his critical dissection of ASIO practice from a criminal
justice perspective. The ‘request’ to go to the park was
an unlawful
arrest. Ul-Haque should have been informed of his rights, taken to a police
station, detained according to regulations
and had his interview recorded. The
failure to specify his alleged offence and to tell him instead that “he
knew what he had
done wrong” was “reminiscent of Kafka”
(ibid., para 31), while “to conduct an extensive interview with the
accused, keeping him incommunicado, under colour of the (search) warrant, was a
gross breach of the powers given to the officers
under the warrant”
(ibid., para 44). The interviewers’ ‘prompting’ of Ul-Haque
was condemned as bad interviewing
practice: according to the judge, “the
ASIO officers told him when they thought he was not telling the truth and told
him,
or suggested, what the truth was” which was a method not used by
police because it is “calculated to obtain what the
suspect believes the
interrogator wants to hear ... It is inevitable that the truth of what is said
is likely – if not certainly
– to be adversely affected”
(paras. 46, 102).
According to the judge, the ASIO officers’ conduct
did not merely affect the admissibility of evidence from the interviews with
Ul-Haque: it included a string of criminal offences – false imprisonment,
kidnapping, and assault which were intentionally
committed (ibid., paras.
59,61). These assessments were firmly located in a context of constitutional
principle - the requirement
of legal authorization for the executive to
interfere with an individual’s liberty (ibid., para 60). The conduct of
the ASIO
officers was
grossly improper and constituted an unjustified and unlawful interference with the personal liberty of the accused (and) was a gross interference by the agents of the state with the accused’s legal rights as a citizen, rights which he has whether he be suspected of criminal conduct or not and whether he is a Muslim or not. Furthermore, the conduct was deliberately engaged in for the purpose of overbearing the accused in the hope that he would co-operate’ (ibid., pars. 62, 95).
It was made clear that the Organisation
was responsible for the individual officers’ misconduct was made clear:
“The impropriety
... was grave. There is no suggestion that the officers
acted contrary to ASIO protocols and good reason for thinking that they did
not” (ibid., para 105)
As in Haneef’s case, electronic
recording assisted the defence. While the ASIO interrogations in the park, house
and car were
not contemporaneously recorded, that by the AFP at the police
station was audio-visually recorded, allowing the judge to make an
assessment of
Ul-Haque’s demeanour and manner of answering questions: “The
overwhelming impression that I got from watching
the interview is that the
accused was cowed” (ibid., para 73). This contributed to his assessment
that the negative answers
which Ul-Haque gave to the routine questions about
threats, promises or inducements at the interview’s close were made
because
“he just decided he was going to be compliant and wanted the
interview to end” (ibid., para 75). He regarded the questions
designed to
expose any threats, promises or inducements as “an empty formality”
(ibid., para 92). The judge recognised
the strangeness of the legal fiction
that any suspect whose will has been overwhelmed by threats, promises or
inducements during
an interview will be able to slough off their effects and to
answer the concluding questions genuinely.
iv. Three cases
These are very different cases: Thomas had, on his own account, been significantly involved with terrorist organisations and was a legitimate subject of investigation; Haneef’s distant family connection appears to have been enough to excite Australian politicians making political capital out of a ’terrorist’ drama and security agencies eager to show their worth; in the case of Ul-Haque, it appears that the investigation was conducted primarily to get Ul-Haque’s cooperation in collecting and providing information about others and, when this cooperation was refused, punishing by prosecution.. What connects them for present purposes is their illustration of the uncomfortable relationship between criminal justice and control process paradigms and the central, controversial role played by interrogation.
THE RESOURCES AND LIMITS OF LAW
The criminal justice paradigm is not dead when there
are responsible, independent professionals who take its principles and values
seriously. Thomas’s, Ul-Haque’s and Haneef’s lawyers provide
an excellent example of the long tradition of lawyers
who, refusing to be
intimidated, rely on the basic principles of the rule of law and natural
justice. Haneef’s lawyers deserve
particular comment: refusing to be swept
along in the political and media hysteria about their client, they insisted on
due process
and took the fight to the authorities by releasing the interview
records. The legal principles which provide the motivation for lawyers
such as
these are not complicated: a fair hearing according to law before an independent
judge applying, in a criminal case, the
principles of criminal justice outlined
above.
As this statement indicates, judicial officers play a pivotal role.
The justices of the Victorian Court of Appeal who heard Thomas’s
appeal,
the Queensland magistrate who granted Haneef bail and the New South Wales judge
in Ul-Haque’s case can proudly take
their places as members of a group
identified by Dyzenhaus and Thwaites : “(t)here seems to be something like
a judicial ‘coalition
of the willing’ forming – judges
prepared to uphold the rule of law in the face of executive claims about
national security”
(2007: 10). There is certainly evidence in the
judgements quoted above of judges who are uneasy about current trends and who
are
prepared to challenge governments over aspects of them.
Some governments
have expressed concern about the limitation or exclusion of legality from
responses to terrorism. This frequently
finds expression in calls for the
rhetoric of war to be abandoned, and for countering terrorism to be seen as a
task for law enforcement
(Wilson, ed. 2005). What ‘law enforcement’
means in this context is unsettled, with police and security over-lapping,
cooperating, and occasionally squabbling.
However, law has familiar limits
as a restraint on power. Court cases are expensive and slow. Lawyers acting for
the prosecution too
often resemble government agents rather than independent
professionals. Too many of the heroic judicial affirmations of freedom have
come
from judges in dissenting judgements. Even if such judges carry the majority,
courts can rarely have the final say: governments
and parliaments can respond to
judicial decisions which they do not like by undermining them by legislative
action or by turning
to administrative rather than judicial means of control.
They are particularly able to do so in a jurisdiction like Australia which
has
very limited constitutional protections of individual rights. For example,
Thomas may not have been convicted, but he was made
subject to an administrative
control order (which the High Court found to be legal in Thomas v Mowbray [2007]
HCA 33). Ironically, reliance on law may serve to push state action outside the
reach of legal principle, as what was previously unacceptable
is legalised. As
Lynch concludes pessimistically, legal systems around the world are
“undergoing a rapid re-adjustment in order
to respond to the post 9/11
world” (2007: 231-2)
Courts are increasingly attacked if they give any
indication of being “soft on terror” (Lynch, 2006). The judgements
in
the cases considered here attracted considerable criticism from popular
media, although some of the quality press supported them.
Of more concern is the
official response: to date, there has been no recognition by the Australian
Government of the judicial critiques,
far less any prosecution or disciplining
of officers for demonstrated misconduct. Security authorities do not see
acknowledgement
of legality as an appropriate response to these court rulings.
Finding ways around them seems more appealing: the Australian Federal
Police
Commissioner declared that “Both in the UK and Australia we are testing
the courts. We make no apologies for that, ..
it’s part of the work police
do ... and will help prevent a (terrorist) attack
here”.[4] Action
has been threatened against lawyers who challenge the authorities. For example,
Stephen Keim, Dr Haneef’s barrister.
had to defend himself against
allegations that he had broken professional conduct rules in the way he released
interview tapes to
the media. The official response to the judge’s
criticisms in the Ul-Haque case was not to take action against the police and
ASIO officers, but to launch an official complaint against the judge.
CONCLUSION
The vulnerability of the criminal justice paradigm to executive action and legislative change leads to a pessimistic conclusion. It is perhaps appropriate to end by referring to the cases of the two Australians who were held at Guantanamo Bay, Mamdouh Habib and David Hicks (Sales, 2007). Habib was released without charge, apparently because US authorities did not welcome the prospect of more public scrutiny of what happened to him in Egyptian jails during a lengthy stop-off on his rendered passage to Cuba. At the time of writing, Hicks is the only sometime detainee of Guantanamo Bay who has been ‘convicted’. In a mere façade of legality, confessions produced by years of interrogation led to a plea of guilty to crimes which did not exist, in a court which was not a court, in a place which the US Government had tried to isolate from international law. This guilty plea meant that neither his military ‘commission’ nor, a fortiori a real court, examined the means by which the confessions underlying it were obtained. At the time of writing, Hicks has just been released from the Australian jail where he spent the last few months of detention, apparently broken, not by torture, but by prolonged detention often in isolation. Yet even in this case, the strength of legal principle became evident in the unlikely figure of Hicks’s American army lawyer, Major Michael Mori, who, along with a team of other lawyers (Stafford Smith, 2007) fought for his client skilfully and at very considerable personal cost. Both Habib and Hicks are now subject to indefinite security surveillance and administrative control orders.
Acknowledgements
I am grateful to my colleagues Professor Jill
Hunter and Dr Andrew Lynch for their advice and assistance. My account of
Thomas’s
case draws heavily on Dr Lynch’s published research.
References
Chesney, R.M. & Goldsmith, J.L. (2008, forthcoming) ‘Terrorism and the convergence of criminal and military detention models’ Stanford Law Review 60: 1-59.
Dershowitz, A. (2006) Preemption (New York: WW Norton)
Dixon, D (1997) Law in Policing: Legal Regulation and Police Practices (Oxford: Clarendon)
--- (2007) Interrogating Images: Audio-visually Recorded Police Questioning of Suspects (with G.Travis) (Sydney: Institute of Criminology)
--- (2008, forthcoming) ‘Authorise and regulate: a comparative perspective on the rise and fall of a regulatory strategy’, in E.Cape & R.Young, eds. Regulating Policing (Oxford: Hart)
Dyzenhause, D & Thwaites, R (2007) ‘Legality and emergency – the judiciary in a time of terror’, in Lynch et al. eds 2007: 9-27
Garland, D. (2001) The Culture of Control (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
Gelles, MG, McFadden, R, Borum, R & Vossekuil, B (2006) ‘Al-Qaeda-related subjects: a law enforcement perspective’, in Williamson, ed., 2006: 23-41.
James, N (2007) ‘Torture: what is it, will it work and can be justified?’ in Lynch et al eds. 2007: 155-64
Lynch, A (2006) ‘Maximising the drama: “Jihad Jack”, the Court of Appeal and the Australian media’ Adelaide Law Review 27: 311-34.
---- (2007) ‘Achieving security, respecting rights and maintaining the rule of law’, in Lynch et al. eds. 2007: 222-33
Lynch, A., Macdonald, E., & Williams, G. eds (2007) Law and Liberty in the War on Terror (Leichhardt: Federation)
Mackey, C. with G.Miller (2004) The Interrogator’s War (London: John Murray
Pearse, J.J. (2006) ‘The interrogation of terrorist suspects: the banality of torture’, in Williamson, ed. 2006: 64-83.
Sales. L. (2007) Detainee 002: The Case of David Hicks (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press)
Stafford Smith, C. (2007) Eight O’Clock Ferry to the Windward Side: Seeking Justice in Guantanamo Bay (New York: Nation Books)
Strauss, M. (2003) ‘Torture’, New York Law School Law Review 48: 201-74.
Williamson, T., (2006) ‘Investigative interviewing and human rights the war on terrorism’, in Williamson, ed. 2006: 3-22.
Williamson, T. ed (2006) Investigative Interviewing (Cullompton: Willan).
Wilson, R.A., ed (2005) Human Rights in the ‘War on Terror’ (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Zedner, L. (2005a) Criminal Justice, (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
---- (2005b) ‘Securing Liberty in the Face of Terror, Journal of Law and Society, 32: 507-33.
---- (2007a) ‘Pre-crime and post-criminology?’ Theoretical Criminology 11: 261-81.
---- (2007b) ‘Fixing the future? Precaution and the pre-emptive turn in criminal justice’ University of New South Wales Law Faculty seminar, 15 August 2007.
Cases
DPP v Thomas [2006] VSC 243
R v Thomas [2006] VSCA 165
R v Ul-Haque [2007] NSWSC 1251
Thomas v Mowbray [2007] HCA 33
[*] Dean, Faculty of
Law, UNSW, Sydney 2052;
d.dixon@unsw.edu.au
[1]
For definitive discussion of these trends, see Garland 2001; Zedner, 2007a,
2007b. For a more positive view, see Dershowitz
2006.
[2] At the time
of writing, the U.S. President has just vetoed a Bill which would have
prohibited the CIA from using interrogation methods
such as water-boarding:
‘Veto of Bill on CIA tactics affirms Bush’s legacy’ New
York Times 9 March 2008. Meanwhile, Khalid Sheik Mohammed has been charged
with murdering the 9/11 victims on the basis, inter alia, of confessions
obtained by water-boarding.
[3] These are
available on the website of The Hindu, at www.hindu.com/nic/0058/haneef.htm
(viewed 23 January
2008).
[4]
“Keelty attacked for ‘court testing’” The
Australian 17 December 2007, p3.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/UNSWLRS/2008/24.html